15.11.2013 Views

Neo-Platonism - Grand Lodge Bet-El

Neo-Platonism - Grand Lodge Bet-El

Neo-Platonism - Grand Lodge Bet-El

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong><br />

There is certainly no accident in a man’s becoming a slave<br />

nor is he taken prisoner in war by chance<br />

nor is outrage done on his body without due cause<br />

but he was once the doer of that which he now suffers.<br />

Each soul comes down to a body made ready for it<br />

according to its resemblance to the soul’s disposition.<br />

He who finds fault with the nature of universe<br />

does not know what he is doing<br />

nor how far his arrogance is taking him.<br />

- Plotinus<br />

<strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong> is a modern term used to designate the period of Platonic philosophy beginning with<br />

the work of Plotinus and ending with the closing of the Platonic Academy by the Emperor Justinian<br />

in 529 CE. This brand of <strong>Platonism</strong>, which is often described as ‘mystical’ or religious in nature,<br />

developed outside the mainstream of Academic <strong>Platonism</strong>. The origins of <strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong> can be<br />

traced back to the era of Hellenistic syncretism which spawned such movements and schools of<br />

thought as Gnosticism and the Hermetic tradition. A major factor in this syncretism, and one which<br />

had an immense influence on the development of Platonic thought was the introduction of the Jewish<br />

Scriptures into Greek intellectual circles via the translation known as the Septuagint. The encounter<br />

between the creation narrative of Genesis and the cosmology of Plato’s Timaeus set in motion a long<br />

tradition of cosmological theorizing that finally culminated in the grand scheme of Plotinus’<br />

Enneads. Plotinus’ two major successors, Porphyry and Iamblichus, each developed, in their own<br />

way, certain isolated aspects of Plotinus’ thought, but neither of them developed a rigorous<br />

philosophy to match that of their master. It was Proclus who, shortly before the closing of the<br />

Academy, bequeathed a systematic Platonic philosophy upon the world that in certain ways<br />

approached the sophistication of Plotinus. Finally, in the work of the so-called Pseudo-Dionysius, we<br />

find a grand synthesis of Platonic philosophy and Christian theology that was to exercise an<br />

immense influence on mediaeval mysticism and Renaissance Humanism.


Table of Contents<br />

2. What is <strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong>?<br />

3. Plotinian <strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong><br />

a. Contemplation and Creation<br />

b. Nature and Personality<br />

c. Salvation and the Cosmic Process<br />

♦ Plotinus’ Last Words<br />

d. The Achievement of Plotinus<br />

♦ The Plotinian Synthesis<br />

4. Porphyry and Iamblichus<br />

a. The Nature of the Soul<br />

♦ The (re)turn to Astrology<br />

b. The Quest for Transcendence<br />

♦ Theurgy and the Distrust of Dialectic<br />

5. Proclus and Pseudo-Dionysius<br />

a. Being — Becoming — Being<br />

b. The God Beyond Being<br />

6. Appendix: The Renaissance Platonists<br />

7. References<br />

1. What is <strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong>?<br />

The term ‘<strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong>’ is a modern construction. Plotinus, who is often considered the ‘founder’ of<br />

<strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong>, would not have considered himself a “new” Platonist in any sense, but simply an<br />

expositor of the doctrines of Plato. That this required him to formulate an entirely new philosophical<br />

system would not have been viewed by him as a problem, for it was, in his eyes, precisely what the<br />

Platonic doctrine required. In a sense, this is true, for as early as the Old Academy we find Plato’s<br />

successors struggling with the proper interpretation of his thought, and arriving at strikingly<br />

different conclusions. Also, in the Hellenistic era, certain Platonic ideas were taken up by thinkers of<br />

various loyalties — Jewish, Gnostic, Christian — and worked up into new forms of expression that<br />

varied quite considerably from what Plato actually wrote in his Dialogues. Should this lead us to the<br />

conclusion that these thinkers were any less ‘loyal’ to Plato than were the members of the Academy<br />

(in its various forms throughout the centuries preceding Plotinus)? No; for the multiple and often<br />

contradictory uses made of Platonic ideas is a testament to the universality of Plato’s thought — that<br />

is, its ability to admit of a wide variety of interpretations and applications. In this sense, <strong>Neo</strong>-<br />

<strong>Platonism</strong> may be said to have begun immediately after Plato’s death, when new approaches to his<br />

philosophy were being broached. Indeed, we already see a hint, in the doctrines of Xenocrates (the<br />

second head of the Old Academy) of a type of salvation theory involving the unification of the two<br />

parts of the human soul — the “Olympian” or heavenly, and the “Titanic” or earthly (Dillon 1977, p.<br />

27). If we accept Frederick Coplestone’s description of <strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong> as “the intellectualist reply to<br />

the … yearning for personal salvation” (Copleston 1962, p. 216) we can already locate the beginning of<br />

this reply as far back as the Old Academy, and <strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong> would then not have begun with<br />

Plotinus. However, it is not clear that Xenocrates’ idea of salvation involved the individual; it is<br />

quite possible that he was referring to a unified human nature in an abstract sense. In any case, the<br />

early Hermetic-Gnostic tradition is certainly to an extent Platonic and later Gnosticism and<br />

Christian Logos theology markedly so. If an intellectual reply to a general yearning for personal<br />

salvation is what characterizes <strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong>, then the highly intellectual Gnostics and Christians<br />

of the Late Hellenistic era must be given the title of <strong>Neo</strong>-Platonist. However, if we are to be rigorous<br />

and define <strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong> as the synthesis of various more or less ‘Platonistic’ ideas into a grand<br />

expression of platonic philosophy, then Plotinus must be considered the founder of <strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong>.<br />

Yet we must not forget that these Platonizing Christian, Gnostic, Jewish, and other ‘pagan’ thinkers<br />

provided the necessary speculative material to make this synthesis possible.


2. Plotinian <strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong><br />

The great third century thinker and ‘founder’ of <strong>Neo</strong>-<strong>Platonism</strong>, Plotinus, is responsible for the grand<br />

synthesis of progressive Christian and Gnostic ideas with the traditional Platonic philosophy. He<br />

answered the challenge of accounting for the emergence of a seemingly inferior and flawed cosmos<br />

from the perfect mind of the divinity by declaring outright that all objective existence is but the<br />

external self-expression of an inherently contemplative deity known as the One (to hen), or the Good<br />

(ta kalon). Plotinus compares the expression of the superior godhead with the self-expression of the<br />

individual soul, which proceeds from the perfect conception of a Form (eidos), to the always flawed<br />

expression of this Form in the manner of a materially derived ‘personality’ that risks succumbing to<br />

the demands of divisive discursivity, and so becomes something less than divine. This diminution of<br />

the divine essence in temporality is but a necessary moment of the complete expression of the One.<br />

By elevating the experience of the individual soul to the status of an actualization of a divine Form,<br />

Plotinus succeeded, also, in preserving, if not the autonomy, at least the dignity and ontological<br />

necessity of personality. The Cosmos, according to Plotinus, is not a created order, planned by a deity<br />

on whom we can pass the charge of begetting evil; for the Cosmos is the self-expression of the Soul,<br />

which corresponds, roughly, to Philo’s logos prophorikos, the logos endiathetos of which is the<br />

Intelligence (nous). Rather, the Cosmos, in Plotinian terms, is to be understood as the concrete result<br />

or ‘product’ of the Soul’s experience of its own Mind (nous). Ideally, this concrete expression should<br />

serve the Soul as a reference-point for its own self-conscious existence; however, the Soul all too easily<br />

falls into the error of valuing the expression over the principle (arkhê), which is the contemplation of<br />

the divine Forms. This error gives rise to evil, which is the purely subjective relation of the Soul (now<br />

divided) to the manifold and concrete forms of its expressive act. When the Soul, in the form of<br />

individual existents, becomes thus preoccupied with its experience, Nature comes into being, and the<br />

Cosmos takes on concrete form as the locus of personality.<br />

a. Contemplation and Creation<br />

Hearkening back, whether consciously or not, to the doctrine of Speusippus (Plato’s nephew and<br />

successor in the Academy) .Tat the One is utterly transcendent and “beyond being,” and that the<br />

Dyad is the true first principle (Dillon 1977, p. 12), Plotinus declares that the One is “alone with itself”<br />

and ineffable (cf. Enneads VI.9.6 and V.2.1). The One does not act to produce a cosmos or a spiritual<br />

order, but simply generates from itself, effortlessly, a power (dunamis) which is at once the Intellect<br />

(nous) and the object of contemplation (theôria) of this Intellect. While Plotinus suggests that the One<br />

subsists by thinking itself as itself, the Intellect subsists through thinking itself as other, and therefore<br />

becomes divided within itself: this act of division within the Intellect is the production of Being,<br />

which is the very principle of expression or discursively (Ennead V.1.7). For this reason, the Intellect<br />

stands as Plotinus’ sole First Principle. At this point, the thinking or contemplation of the Intellect is<br />

divided up and ordered into thoughts, each of them subsisting in and for themselves, as autonomous<br />

reflections of the dunam is of the One. These are the Forms (eidê), and out of their inert unity there<br />

arises the Soul, whose task it is to think these Forms discursively and creatively, and to thereby<br />

produce or create a concrete, living expression of the divine Intellect. This activity of the Soul results<br />

in the production of numerous individual souls: living actualizations of the possibilities inherent in<br />

the Forms. Whereas the Intellect became divided within itself through contemplation, the Soul<br />

becomes divided outside of itself, through action (which is still contemplation, according to Plotinus,<br />

albeit the lowest type; cf. Ennead III.8.4), and this division constitutes the Cosmos, which is the<br />

expressive or creative act of the Soul, also referred to as Nature. When the individual soul reflects<br />

upon Nature as its own act, this soul is capable of attaining insight (gnosis) into the essence of<br />

Intellect; however, when the soul views nature as something objective and external — that is, as<br />

something to be experienced or undergone, while forgetting that the soul itself is the creator of this<br />

Nature — evil and suffering ensue. Let us now examine the manner in which Plotinus explains<br />

Nature as the locus of personality.


. Nature and Personality<br />

Contemplation, at the level of the Soul, is for Plotinus a two-way street. The Soul both contemplates,<br />

passively, the Intellect, and reflects upon its own contemplative act by producing Nature and the<br />

Cosmos. The individual souls that become immersed in Nature, as moments of the Soul’s eternal act,<br />

will, ideally, gain a complete knowledge of the Soul in its unity, and even of the Intellect, by<br />

reflecting upon the concrete results of the Soul’s act — that is, upon the externalized, sensible entities<br />

that comprise the physical Cosmos. This reflection, if carried by the individual soul with a memory of<br />

its provenance always in the foreground, will lead to a just governing of the physical Cosmos, which<br />

will make of it a perfect material image of the Intellectual Cosmos, i.e., the realm of the Forms (cf.<br />

Enneads IV.3.7 and IV.8.6). However, things don’t always turn out so well, for individual souls often<br />

“go lower than is needful … in order to light the lower regions, but it is not good for them to go so<br />

far” (Ennead IV.3.17, tr. O’Brien 1964). For when the soul extends itself ever farther into the<br />

indeterminacy of materiality, it gradually loses memory of its divine origin, and comes to identify<br />

itself more and more with its surroundings — that is to say: the soul identifies itself with the results<br />

of the Soul’s act, and forgets that it is, as part of this Soul, itself an agent of the act. This is<br />

tantamount to a relinquishing, by the soul, of its divine nature. When the soul has thus abandoned<br />

itself, it begins to accrue many alien encrustations, if you will, that make of it something less than<br />

divine. These encrustations are the ‘accidents’ (in the Aristotelian sense) of personality. And yet the<br />

soul is never completely lost, for, as Plotinus insists, the soul needs simply “think upon essential<br />

being” in order to return to itself, and continue to exist authentically as a governor of the Cosmos<br />

(Ennead IV.8.4-6). The memory of the personality that this wandering soul possessed must be<br />

forgotten in order for it to return completely to its divine nature; for if it were remembered, we<br />

would have to say, contradictorily, that the soul holds a memory of what occurred during its state of<br />

forgetfulness! So in a sense, Plotinus holds that individual personalities are not maintained at the<br />

level of Soul. However, if we understand personality as more than just a particular attitude<br />

attached to a concrete mode of existence, and rather view it as the sum total of experiences reflected<br />

upon in intellect, then souls most certainly retain their personalities, even at the highest level, for<br />

they persist as thoughts within the divine Mind (cp. Ennead IV.8.5). The personality that one<br />

acquires in action (the lowest type of contemplation) is indeed forgotten and dissolved, but the<br />

‘personality’ or persistence in intellect that one achieves through virtuous acts most definitely<br />

endures (Ennead IV.3.32).<br />

c. Salvation and the Cosmic Process<br />

Plotinus, like his older contemporary Christian philosopher, who was originally from Alexandria,<br />

views the descent of the soul into the material sphere as a necessary moment in the unfolding of the<br />

divine Intellect, or God. For this reason, the descent itself is not an evil, for it is a reflection of God’s<br />

essence. Both Origen and Plotinus place the blame for experiencing this descent as an evil squarely<br />

upon the individual soul. Of course, these thinkers held, respectively, quite different views as to why<br />

and how the soul experiences the descent as an evil; but they held one thing in common: that the<br />

rational soul will naturally choose the Good, and that any failure to do so is the result of<br />

forgetfulness or acquired ignorance. But whence this failure? Origen gave what, to Plotinus’ mind,<br />

must have been a quite unsatisfactory answer: that souls pre-existed as spiritual beings, and when<br />

they desired to create or ‘beget’ independently of God, they all fell into error, and languished there<br />

until the coming of Logos Incarnate. This view has more than a little Gnostic flavor to it, which<br />

would have sat ill with Plotinus, who was a great opponent of Gnosticism. The fall of the soul<br />

Plotinus refers, quite simply, to the tension between pure contemplation and divisive action — a<br />

tension that constitutes the natural mode of existence of the soul (cf. Ennead IV.8.6-7). Plotinus tells<br />

us that a thought is only completed or fully comprehended after it has been expressed, for only then<br />

can the thought be said to have passed from potentiality to actuality (Ennead IV.3.30). The question<br />

of whether Plotinus places more value on the potential or the actual is really of no consequence, for<br />

in the Plotinian plêrôma every potentiality generates an activity, and every activity becomes itself


a potential for new activity (cf. Ennead III.8.8); and since the One, which is the goal or object of<br />

desire of all existents, is neither potentiality nor actuality, but “beyond being” (epekeina ousias), it is<br />

impossible to say whether the striving of existents, in Plotinus’ schema, will result in full and<br />

complete actualization, or in a repose of potentiality that will make them like their source. “Likeness<br />

to God as far as possible,” for Plotinus, is really likeness to oneself – authentic existence. Plotinus<br />

leaves it up to the individual to determine what this means.<br />

• Plotinus’ Last Words<br />

In his biography of Plotinus, Porphyry records the last words of his teacher to his students as follows:<br />

“Strive to bring back the god in you to the God in the All” (Porphyry, Life of Plotinus 2, my<br />

translation). After uttering these words, Plotinus, one of the greatest philosophers the world has ever<br />

known, passed away. The simplicity of this final statement seems to be at odds with the intellectual<br />

rigors of Plotinus’ treatises, which challenge — and more often than not vanquish — just about every<br />

prominent philosophical view of the era. But this is only if we take this remark in a mystical or<br />

ecstatic religious sense. Plotinus demanded the utmost level of intellectual clarity in dealing with the<br />

problem of humankind’s relation to the highest principle of existence. Striving for or desiring<br />

salvation was not, for Plotinus, an excuse for simply abandoning oneself to faith or prayer or<br />

unreflective religious rituals; rather, salvation was to be achieved through the practice of<br />

philosophical investigation, of dialectic. The fact that Plotinus, at the end of his life, had arrived at<br />

this very simple formulation, serves to show that his dialectical quest was successful. In his last<br />

treatise, “On the Primal Good” (Ennead I.7), Plotinus is able to assert, in the same breath, that both<br />

life and death are good. He says this because life is the moment in which the soul expresses itself and<br />

revels in the autonomy of the creative act. However, this life, since it is characterized by action,<br />

eventually leads to exhaustion, and the desire, not for autonomous action, but for reposeful<br />

contemplation — of a fulfillment that is purely intellectual and eternal. Death is the relief of this<br />

exhaustion, and the return to a state of contemplative repose. Is this return to the Intellect a return<br />

to potentiality? It is hard to say. Perhaps it is a synthesis of potentiality and actuality: the moment<br />

at which the soul is both one and many, both human and divine. This would constitute Plotinian<br />

salvation — the fulfillment of the exhortation of the dying sage.<br />

d. The Achievement of Plotinus<br />

In the last analysis, what stands as the most important and impressive accomplishment of Plotinus is<br />

the manner in which he synthesized the pure, ‘semi-mythical’ expression of Plato with the logical<br />

rigors of the Peripatetic and Stoic schools, yet without losing sight of philosophy’s most important<br />

task: of rendering the human experience in intelligible and analyzable terms. That Plotinus’ thought<br />

had to take the ‘detour’ through such wildly mystical and speculative paths as Gnosticism and<br />

Christian salvation theology is only proof of his clear-sightedness, thoroughness, and admirable<br />

humanism. For all of his dialectical difficulties and perambulations, Plotinus’ sole concern is with the<br />

well-being (eudemonia) of the human soul. This is, of course, to be understood as an intellectual, as<br />

opposed to a merely physical or even emotional well-being, for Plotinus was not concerned with the<br />

temporary or the temporal. The striving of the human mind for a mode of existence more suited to<br />

its intuited potential than the ephemeral possibilities of this material realm, while admittedly a<br />

striving born of temporality, is nonetheless directed toward a temporal and divine perfection. This is<br />

a striving or desire rendered all the more poignant and worthy of philosophy precisely because it is<br />

born in the depths of existential angst, and not in the primitive ecstasies of unreflective ritual. As<br />

the last true representative of the Greek philosophical spirit, Plotinus is Apollonian, not Dionysian.<br />

His concern is with the intellectual beautification of the human soul, and for this reason his notion of<br />

salvation does not, like Origen’s, imply an eternal state of objective contemplation of the divinity —<br />

for Plotinus, the separation between human and god breaks down, so that when the perfected soul<br />

contemplates itself, it is also contemplating the Supreme.


• The Plotinian Synthesis<br />

Plotinus was faced with the task of defending the true Platonic philosophy, as he understood it,<br />

against the inroads being made, in his time, most of all by Gnostics, but also by orthodox<br />

Christianity. Instead of launching an all-out attack on these new ideas, Plotinus took what was best<br />

from them, in his eyes, and brought these ideas into concert with his own brand of <strong>Platonism</strong>. For<br />

this reason, we are sometimes surprised to see Plotinus, in one treatise, speaking of the cosmos as a<br />

realm of forgetfulness and error, while in another, speaking of the cosmos as the most perfect<br />

expression of the godhead. Once we realize the extent to which certain Gnostic sects went in order to<br />

brand this world as a product of an evil and malignant Demiurge, to whom we owe absolutely no<br />

allegiance, it becomes clear that Plotinus was simply trying to temper the extreme form of an idea<br />

which he himself shared, though in a less radical sense. The feeling of being thrown into a hostile and<br />

alien world is a philosophically valid position from which to begin a critique and investigation of<br />

human existence; indeed, modern existentialist philosophers have often started from this same<br />

premise. However, Plotinus realized that it is not the nature of the human soul to simply escape<br />

from a realm of active engagement with external reality (the cosmos) to a passive receptance of<br />

divine form (within the plêrôma). The Soul, as Plotinus understands it, is an essentially creative<br />

being, and one which understands existence on its own terms. One of the beauties of Plotinus’ system<br />

is that everything he says concerning the nature of the Cosmos (spiritual and physical) can equally<br />

be held of the Soul. Now while it would be false to charge Plotinus with solipsism (or even narcissism,<br />

as one prominent commentator has done; cf. Julia Kristeva in Hadot 1993, p. 11), it would be correct<br />

to say that the entire Cosmos is an analogue of the experience of the Soul, which results in the<br />

attainment of full self-consciousness. The form of Plotinus’ system is the very form by which the Soul<br />

naturally comes to know itself in relation to its acts; and the expression of the Soul will always,<br />

therefore, be a philosophical expression. speaking of the Plotinian synthesis, then, natural dialectic of<br />

the Soul, which takes its own expressions into account, no matter how faulty or incomplete they<br />

appear in retrospect, and weaves them to a cosmic tapestry of noetic images.<br />

4. Porphyry and Iamblichus<br />

Porphyry of Tyr (ca. 233-305 CE) is the most famous pupil of Plotinus. In addition to writing an<br />

introductory summary of his master’s theories (the treatise entitled Launching-Points to the Realm<br />

of Mind), Porphyry also composed the famous Isagoge, an introduction to the Categories of Aristotle,<br />

which came to exercise an immense influence on Mediaeval Scholasticism. The extent of Porphyry’s<br />

investigative interests exceeded that of his teacher, and his so-called “scientific” works, which<br />

survive to this day, include a treatise on music (On Prosody), and two studies of the astronomical<br />

and astrological theories of Claudius Ptolemy (ca. 70-140 CE), On the Harmonics, and an Introduction<br />

to The Astronomy of Ptolemy. He wrote biographies of Pythagoras and Plotinus, and edited and<br />

compiled the latter’s essays into six books, each containing nine treatises, giving them the title<br />

Enneads. Unlike Plotinus, Porphyry was interested primarily in the practical aspect of salvific<br />

striving, and the manner in which the soul could most effectively bring about its transference to<br />

ever higher realms of existence. This led Porphyry to develop a doctrine of ascent to the Intellect by<br />

way of the exercise of virtue (aretê) in the form of ‘good works’. This doctrine may owe its genesis to<br />

Porphyry’s supposed early adherence to Christianity, as attested by the historian Socrates, and<br />

suggested by St. Augustine (cf. Copleston 1962, p. 218). If Porphyry had, at some point, been a<br />

Christian, this would account for his belief in the soul’s objective relation to the divine Mind — an<br />

idea shared by Origen, whom Porphyry knew as a youth (cf. Eusebius, The History of the Church, p.<br />

195) — and would explain his quite un-Plotinian belief in a gradual progress toward perfection, as<br />

opposed to the ‘instant salvation’ proposed by Plotinus (cf. Ennead IV.8.4). Iamblichus of Anjar (d. ca.<br />

330 CE) was a student of Porphyry. He departed from his teacher on more than a few points, most<br />

notably in his insistence on demoting Plotinus’ One (which Porphyry left unscathed, as it were) to the<br />

level of cosmos noêtos, which according to Iamblichus generates the intellectual realm (cosmos<br />

noêros). In this regard, Iamblichus can be said to have either severely misunderstood, or neglected to


even attempt to understand, Plotinus on the important doctrine of contemplation (see above). This<br />

view led Iamblichus to posit a Supreme One even higher than the One of Plotinus, which generates<br />

the Intellectual Cosmos, and yet remains beyond all predication and determinacy. Iamblichus also<br />

made a tripartite division of Soul, positing a cosmic or All-Soul, and two lesser souls, corresponding<br />

to the rational and irrational faculties, respectively. This somewhat gratuitous skewing of the<br />

Plotinian noetic realm also led Iamblichus to posit an array of intermediate spiritual beings between<br />

the lower souls and the intelligible realm — daemons, the souls of heroes, and angels of all sorts. By<br />

placing so much distance between the earthly soul and the intelligible realm, Iamblichus made it<br />

difficult for the would-be philosopher to gain an intuitive knowledge of the higher Soul, although he<br />

insisted that everyone possesses such knowledge, coupled with an innate desire for the Good. In place<br />

of the vivid dialectic of Plotinus, Iamblichus established the practice of Theurgy (theourgia), which<br />

he insists does not draw the gods down to man, but rather renders humankind, “who through<br />

generation are born subject to passion, pure and unchangeable” (On the Mysteries I.12.42; in Fowden<br />

1986, p. 133). Whereas “likeness to God” had meant, for Plotinus, a recollection and perfection of one’s<br />

own divine nature (which is, in the last analysis, identical to nous; cf. Ennead III.4), for Iamblichus<br />

the relation of humankind to the divine is one of subordinate to superior, and so the pagan religious<br />

piety that Plotinus had scorned — “Let the gods come to me, and not I to them,” he had once said (cf.<br />

Porphyry, Life of Plotinus 10) — returns to philosophy with a vengeance. Iamblichus is best known<br />

for his lengthy treatise On the Mysteries. Like Porphyry, he also wrote a biography of Pythagoras.<br />

a. The Nature of the Soul<br />

In his introduction to the philosophy of Plotinus, entitled Launching-Points to the Realm of Mind,<br />

Porphyry remarks that the inclination of the incorporeal Soul toward corporeality “constitutes a<br />

second nature [the irrational soul], which unites with the body” (Launching-Points 18 [1]). This<br />

remark is supposedly a commentary on Ennead IV.2, where Plotinus discusses the relation of the<br />

individual soul to the All-Soul. While it is true that Plotinus often speaks of the individual soul as<br />

being independent of the highest Soul, he does this for illustrative purposes, in order to show how far<br />

into forgetfulness the soul that has become enamored of its act may fall. Yet Plotinus insists time and<br />

again that the individual soul and the All-Soul are one (cf. esp. Ennead IV.1), and that Nature is the<br />

Soul’s expressive act (see above). Irrationality does not constitute, for Plotinus, a “second nature,” but<br />

is merely a flawed exercise of rationality — that is, doxa untempered by episteme – on the part of<br />

the individual soul. Furthermore, the individual soul, which comes to unite with corporeality,<br />

governs and controls the body, making possible discursive knowledge as well as sense-perception.<br />

Uncontrolled pathos is what Plotinus calls irrationality; the soul brings aisthêsis (perceptive<br />

judgment) to corporeality, and so prevents it from sinking into irrational passivity. So what led<br />

Porphyry to make such an interpretative error, if error it was? It is quite possible that Porphyry<br />

had arrived at his own conclusions about the Soul, and tried to square his own theory with what<br />

Plotinus actually taught. One clue to the reason for the ‘misunderstanding’ may possibly lie in<br />

Porphyry’s early involvement with Christianity. While Porphyry himself never tells us that he had<br />

been a Christian, Augustine speaks of him as if he were an apostate, and the historian Socrates states<br />

outright that Porphyry had once been of the Christian faith, telling us that he left the fold in disgust<br />

after being assaulted by a rowdy band of Christians in Caesarea (Copleston 1962, p. 218). In any case,<br />

it is certain that he was acquainted with Plotinus’ older contemporary, the Christian Origen, and<br />

that he had been exposed to Christian doctrine. Indeed, his own spirited attack on Christianity<br />

(“Fifteen Arguments against the Christians,” now preserved only in fragments) shows him to have<br />

possessed a wide knowledge of Holy Scripture, remarkable for a ‘pagan’ philosopher of that era.<br />

Porphyry’s exposure to Christian doctrine, then, would have left him with a view of salvation quite<br />

different from that of Plotinus, who seems never to have paid Christianity much mind. The best<br />

evidence we have for this explanation is Porphyry’s own theory of salvation — and it is remarkably<br />

similar to what we find in Origen! Porphyry’s salvation theory is dependent, like Origen’s, on a<br />

notion of the soul’s objective relation to God, and its consequent striving, not to actualize its own<br />

divine potentiality, but to attain a level of virtue that makes it capable of partaking fully of the


divine essence. This is accomplished through the exercise of virtue, which sets the soul on a gradual<br />

course of progress toward the highest Good. Beginning with simple ‘practical virtues’ (politikai<br />

arêtai) the soul gradually rises to higher levels, eventually attaining what Porphyry calls the<br />

paradeigmatikai arêtai or ‘exemplary virtues’ which make of the soul a living expression of the<br />

divine Mind (cf. Porphyry, Letter to Marcella 29). Note that Porphyry stops the soul’s ascent at nous,<br />

and presumably holds that the ‘saved’ soul will eternally contemplate the infinite power of the One.<br />

If Porphyry’s concern had been with the preservation of personality, then this explanation makes<br />

some sense. However, it is more likely that the true reason for Porphyry’s rejection of the radically<br />

‘hubristic’ theory (at least to pietistic pagans) of the nature of the individual soul held by Plotinus<br />

was a result of his intention to restore dignity to the traditional religion of the Greeks (which had<br />

come under attack not only by Plotinus, but by Christians as well). Evidence of such a program<br />

resides in Porphyry’s allegorical interpretations of Homer and traditional cultic practice, as well as<br />

his possibly apologetic work on Philosophy from Oracles (now lost). Compared to Plotinus, then,<br />

Porphyry was quite the conservative, concerned as he was with maintaining the ancient view of<br />

humankind’s relatively humble position in the cosmic hierarchy, over against Plotinus’ view that the<br />

soul is a god, owing little more than a passing nod to its ‘noble brethren’ in the heavens.<br />

• The (re)turn to Astrology<br />

One of the results of Porphyry’s conservative position toward traditional religious practice and<br />

belief was the ‘return’ to the doctrine that the stars and planets are capable of affecting and<br />

ordering human life. Plotinus argued that since the individual soul is one with the All-Soul, it is in<br />

essence a co-creator of the Cosmos, and therefore not really subject to the laws governing the Cosmos<br />

— for the soul is the source and agent of those laws! Therefore, a belief in astrology was, for Plotinus,<br />

absurd, since if the soul turned to beings dependent upon its own law — i.e., the stars and planets —<br />

in order to know itself, then it would only end up knowing aspects of its own act, and would never<br />

return to itself in full self-consciousness. Furthermore, as we have seen, Plotinian salvation was<br />

instantly available to the soul, if only it would turn its mind to “essential being” (see above); because<br />

of this, Plotinus saw no reason to bring the stars and planets into the picture. For Porphyry,<br />

however, who believed that the soul must gradually work toward salvation, knowledge of the<br />

operations of the heavenly bodies and their relation to humankind would have been an important<br />

tool in gaining ever higher levels of virtue. In fact, Porphyry seems to have held the view that the<br />

soul receives certain “powers” from each of the planets — right judgment from Saturn, proper<br />

exercise of the will from Jupiter, impulse from Mars, opinion and imagination from the Sun, and<br />

(what else?) sensuous desire from Venus; from the Moon the soul receives the power of physical<br />

production (cf. Hegel, p. 430) — and that these powers enable to the soul to know things both earthly<br />

and heavenly. This theoretical knowledge of the powers of the planets, then, would have made the<br />

more practical knowledge of astrology quite useful and meaningful for an individual soul seeking to<br />

know itself as such. The usefulness of astrology for Porphyry, in this regard, probably resided in its<br />

ability to permit an individual, through an analysis of his birth chart, to know which planet — and<br />

therefore which “power” — exercised the dominant influence on his life. In keeping with the ancient<br />

Greek doctrine of the “golden mean,” the task of the individual would then be to work to bring to the<br />

fore those other “powers” — each present to a lesser degree in the soul, but still active — and thereby<br />

achieve a balance or sôphrosunê that would render the soul more capable of sharing in the divine<br />

Mind. The art of astrology, it must be remembered, was in wide practice in the Hellenistic world,<br />

and Plotinus’ rejection of it was an exception that was by no means the rule. Plotinus’ views on<br />

astrology apparently found few adherents, even among Platonists, for we see not only Porphyry, but<br />

also (to an extent) Iamblichus and even Proclus declaring its value — the latter being responsible for<br />

a paraphrase of Claudius Ptolemy’s astrological compendium known as the Tetrabiblos or sometimes<br />

simply as The Astronomy. In addition to penning a commentary on Ptolemy’s tome, Porphyry also<br />

wrote his own Introduction to Astronomy (by which is apparently meant “Astrology,” the modern<br />

distinction not holding in Hellenistic times). Unfortunately, this work no longer survives intact.


. The Quest for Transcendence<br />

The philosophy of Plotinus was highly discursive, meaning that it operated on the assumption that<br />

the highest meaning, the most profound truth (even a so-called mystical truth) is translatable,<br />

necessarily, into language; and furthermore, that any and every experience only attains its full<br />

value as meaning when it has reached expression in the form of language. This idea, of course, placed<br />

the One always beyond the discursive understanding of the human soul, since the One was<br />

proclaimed, by Plotinus, to be not only beyond discursive knowledge, but also the very source and<br />

possibility of such knowledge. According to Plotinus, then, any time the individual soul expresses a<br />

certain truth in language, this very act is representative of the power of the One. This notion of the<br />

simultaneous intimate proximity of the One to the soul, and, paradoxically, its extreme<br />

transcendence and ineffability, is possible only within the confines of a purely subjective and<br />

introspective philosophy like that of Plotinus; and since such a philosophy, by its very nature, cannot<br />

appeal to common, external perceptions, it is destined to remain the sole provenance of the sensitive<br />

and enlightened few. Porphyry did not want to admit this, and so he found himself seeking, as St.<br />

Augustine tells us, “a universal way (universalem viam) for the liberation of the soul” (City of God<br />

10.32, in Fowden, p. 132), believing, as he did, that no such way had yet been discovered by or within<br />

philosophy. This did not imply, for Porphyry, a wholesale rejection of the Plotinian dialectic in favor<br />

of a more esoteric process of salvation; but it did lead Porphyry (see above) to look to astrology as a<br />

means of orienting the soul toward its place in the cosmos, and thereby allowing it to achieve the<br />

desired salvation in the most efficacious manner possible. Iamblichus, on the other hand, rejected<br />

even Porphyry’s approach, in favor of a path toward the divinity that is more worthy of priests<br />

(hieratikoi) than philosophers; for Iamblichus believed that not only the One, but all the gods and<br />

demigods, exceed and transcend the individual soul, making it necessary for the soul seeking<br />

salvation to call upon the superior beings to aid it in its progress. This is accomplished, Iamblichus<br />

tells us, by “the perfective operation of unspeakable acts (erga) correctly performed … acts which are<br />

beyond all understanding (huper pasan noêsin)” and which are “intelligible only to the gods” (On the<br />

Mysteries II.11.96-7, in Fowden, p. 132). These ritualistic acts and the ‘logic’ underlying them<br />

Iamblichus are in terms “Theurgy” (theourgia). These Theurgy acts are necessary, for Iamblichus,<br />

because he is convinced that philosophy, which is based solely upon thought (ennoia) — and thought,<br />

we must remember, is always an accomplishment of the individual mind, and hence discursive — is<br />

unable to reach that which is beyond thought. The practice of Theurgy, then, becomes a way for the<br />

soul to experience the presence of the divinity, instead of merely thinking or conceptualizing the<br />

godhead. Porphyry took issue with this view, in his Letter to Anebo, which is really a criticism of the<br />

ideas of his pupil, Iamblichus, where he stated that, since Theurgy is a physical process, it cannot<br />

possibly translate into a spiritual effect. Iamblichus’ on the Mysteries was written as a reply to<br />

Porphyry’s criticisms, but the defense of the pupil did not succeed in vanquishing the persistent<br />

attacks of the master. While both Porphyry and Iamblichus recognized, to a lesser and greater<br />

extent, respectively, the limitations of the Plotinian dialectic, Porphyry held firm to the idea that<br />

since the divinity is immaterial it can only be grasped in a noetic fashion — i.e., discursively (and<br />

even astrology, in spite of its meditative capacity, is still an intellectual exercise, open to dialectic<br />

and narratization); Iamblichus, adhering roughly to the same view, nevertheless argued that the<br />

human soul must not think god on its own terms, but must allow itself to be transformed by the<br />

penetrating essence of god, of which the soul partakes through rituals intended to transform the<br />

particularized, fragmented soul into a being that is “pure and unchangeable” (cf. On the Mysteries<br />

I.12.42; Fowden, p. 133).<br />

• Theurgy and the Distrust of Dialectic<br />

According to the schema of Plotinian dialectic, the ‘stance’ of the individual soul is the sole source of<br />

truth certainty, being a judging faculty dependent always upon the higher Soul. From the<br />

perspective of one who believes that the soul is immersed in Nature, instead of recognizing, as<br />

Plotinus did, the soul’s status as an intimate governor of Nature (which is the Soul’s own act),


dialectic may very well appear as a solipsistic (and therefore faulty) attempt on the part of an<br />

individual mind to know its reality by imposing conceptual structures and strictures upon the<br />

phenomena that constitute this reality. Iamblichus believed that since every individual soul is<br />

immersed in the ‘bodily element,’ no soul is capable of understanding the divine nature through the<br />

pure exercise of human reason — for reason itself, at the level of the human soul-body composite, is<br />

tainted by the changeable nature of matter, and therefore incapable of rising to that perfect<br />

knowledge that is beyond all change (cp. Plato, Phaedrus 247 e). Dialectic, then, as the soul’s attempt<br />

to know reality, is seen by Iamblichus as an attempt by an already fallen being to lead itself up out<br />

of the very locus of its own forgetfulness. Now Iamblichus does not completely reject dialectical<br />

reason; he simply requests that it be tempered by an appeal to intermediate divinities, who will aid<br />

the fallen soul in its ascent back towards the Supreme Good. The practice of ritualistic Theurgy is the<br />

medium by which the fallen soul ascends to a point at which it becomes capable of engaging in a<br />

meaningful dialectic with the divinity. This dependence upon higher powers nevertheless negates the<br />

soul’s own innate ability to think itself as god, and so we may say that Iamblichus’ ideas represent a<br />

decisive break with the philosophy of Plotinus.<br />

5. Proclus and Pseudo-Dionysius<br />

Proclus (410-485 CE) is, next to Plotinus, the most accomplished and rigorous of the <strong>Neo</strong>-Platonists.<br />

Born in Constantinople, he studied philosophy in Athens, and through diligent effort rose to the rank<br />

of head teacher or ‘scholars’ of that great school. In addition to his accomplishments in philosophy,<br />

Proclus was also a religious Universalist, who had him initiated into all the mystery religions being<br />

practiced during his time. This was doubtless due to the influence of Iamblichus, whom Proclus held<br />

in high esteem (cf. Proclus, Theology of Plato III; in Hegel, p. 432). The philosophical expression of<br />

Proclus is more precise and logically ordered than that of Plotinus. Indeed, Proclus posits the<br />

Intellect (nous) as the culmination of the productive act (paragein) of the One; this is in opposition to<br />

Plotinus, who described the Intellect as proceeding directly from the One, thereby placing Mind<br />

before Thought, and so making thought the process by which the Intellect becomes alienated from<br />

itself, thus requiring the salvific act in order to attain the fulfillment of Being, which is, for Plotinus,<br />

the return of Intellect to itself. Proclus understands the movement of existence as a tripartite<br />

progression beginning with an abstract unity, passing into a multiplicity that is identified with Life,<br />

and returning again to a unity that is no longer merely abstract, but now actualized as an eternal<br />

manifestation of the godhead. What constituted, for Plotinus, the salvific drama of human existence<br />

is, for Proclus, simply the logical, natural order of things. However, by thus removing the yearning<br />

for salvation from human existence, as something to be accomplished, positively, Proclus is ignoring<br />

or overly intellectualizing, if you will, an existential aspect of human existence that is as real as it is<br />

powerful. Plotinus recognized the importance of the salvific drive for the realization of true<br />

philosophy, making philosophy a means to an end; Proclus utilizes philosophy, rather, more in the<br />

manner of a useful, descriptive language by which a thinker may describe the essential realities of a<br />

merely contingent existence. In this sense, Proclus is more faithful to the ‘letter’ of Plato’s Dialogues;<br />

but for this same reason he fails to rise to the ‘spirit’ of the Platonic philosophy. Proclus’ major works<br />

include commentaries on: Plato’s, Timaeus, Republic, Parmenides, Alcibiades I, and the Cratylus. He<br />

also wrote treatises on the Theology of Plato, On Providence, and On the Subsistence of Evil. His most<br />

important work is undoubtedly the <strong>El</strong>ements of Theology, which contains the clearest his ideas.<br />

a. Being — Becoming — Being<br />

We found, in Plotinus, an explanation and expression of a cosmos that involved a gradual<br />

development from all but static unity toward eventual alienation — a moment at which the active<br />

soul must make the profound decision to renounce autonomous existence and re-merge with the<br />

source of all Being, or else remain forever in the darkness of forgetfulness and error. Salvation, for<br />

Plotinus, was relatively easy to accomplish, but never guaranteed. For Proclus, on the other hand,<br />

the arkhê or ‘ruling beginning’ of all Life is the ‘One-in-itself’ (to auto hen), or that which is


esponsible for the ordering of all existents, insofar as existence is, in the last analysis, the sovereign<br />

act or expression of this primordial unity or monad. The expression of this One is perfectly balanced,<br />

being a trinity containing, as distinct expressions, each moment of self-realization of this One; and<br />

each of these moments, according to Proclus, have the structure of yet another trinity. The first<br />

trinity corresponds to the limit, which is the guide and reference-point of all further manifestations;<br />

the second to the unlimited, which is also Life or the productive power (dunamis); and the third,<br />

finally, to the ‘mixture’ (mikton, diakosmos), which is the self-reflective moment of return during<br />

which the soul realizes itself as a thinking — i.e., living — entity. Thought is, therefore, the<br />

culmination of Life and the fulfillment of being. Thought is also the reason (logos) that binds these<br />

triadic unities together in a grand harmonious plêrôma, if you will. Being, for Proclus, is that divine<br />

self-presence, “shut up without development and maintained in strict isolation” (Hegel, p. 446) which<br />

is the object of Life’s thinking; this ‘object’ gives rise to that thinking which leads, eventually, to<br />

understanding (nous), which is the thought of being, and appears (ekphanôs), always, as ‘being’s<br />

begetter’. When the circle is completed, and reflected upon, logically, we are met with the following<br />

onto-cosmological schema: thought (noêtos, also known as ‘Being’) giving rise to its “negative” which<br />

is thinking (Hegel, p. 393) and the thought ‘it is’ (noêtos kai noêros), produces its own precise<br />

reflection — ‘pure thinking’ — and this reflection is the very manifestation (phanerôsis) of the deity<br />

within the fluctuating arena of individual souls. Being is eternal and static precisely because it<br />

always returns to itself as being; and ‘Becoming’ is the conceptual term for this process, which<br />

involves the cyclical play between that which is and is not, at any given time. “[T]he thought of<br />

every man is identical with the existence of every man, and each is both the thought and the<br />

existence” (Proclus, Platonic Theology III., in Hegel, p. 449). The autonomous drive toward<br />

dissolution, which is so germane to the soul as such, is wiped away by Proclus, for his dialectic is<br />

impeccably clean. However, he does not account for the yearning for the infinite (as does Plotinus)<br />

and the consequent existential desire for productive power falls on its face before the supreme god of<br />

autonomous creation — which draws all existents into its primeval web of dissolution.<br />

b. The God beyond Being<br />

Very little is known about the life of the so-called Pseudo-Dionysius. For many centuries, the<br />

writings of this mystical philosopher were believed to have been from the pen of none other<br />

Dionysius, the disciple of St. Paul. Later scholarship has shed considerable doubt on this claim, and<br />

most modern scholars believe this author to have been active during the late fifth century CE.<br />

Indeed, the earliest reference to the Dionysian Corpus that we possess is from 533 CE. There is no<br />

mention of this author’s work before this date. Careful study of the Pseudo-Dionysian writings has<br />

uncovered many parallels between the theurgical doctrines of Iamblichus, and the triadic<br />

metaphysical schema of Proclus. Yet what we witness in these writings is the attempt by a thinker<br />

who is at once religiously sensitive and philosophically engaged to bring the highly developed<br />

<strong>Platonism</strong> of his time into line with a Christian theological tradition that was apparently persisting<br />

on the fringes of orthodoxy. To this extent, we may refer to the Pseudo-Dionysius as a ‘decadent,’ for<br />

he (or she?) was writing at a time when the heyday of <strong>Platonism</strong> had attained the status of a palaios<br />

logos (‘ancient teaching’) to be, not merely commented upon, but savored as an aesthetic monument<br />

to an era already long past. It is important to note, in this regard, that the writings of Pseudo-<br />

Dionysius do not contain any theoretical arguments or dialectical moments, but simply many subtle<br />

variations on the apophatic/kataphatic theology for which our writer is renowned. Indeed, he writes<br />

as if his readers already know, and are merely in need of clarification. His message is quite simple,<br />

and is manifestly distilled from the often cumbersome doctrines of earlier thinkers (especially<br />

Iamblichus and Proclus). Pseudo-Dionysius professes a God who is beyond all distinctions, and who<br />

even transcends the means utilized by human beings to reach Him. For Pseudo-Dionysius, the Holy<br />

Trinity (which is probably analogous to Proclus’ highest trinity, see above) serves as a “guide” to the<br />

human being who seeks not only to know but to unite with “him who is beyond all being and<br />

knowledge” (Pseudo-Dionysius, The Mystical Theology 997A-1000A, tr. C. Luibheid 1987). In the


expression of the Pseudo-Dionysius the yearning for the infinite reaches a poetical form that at once<br />

fulfills and exceeds philosophy.<br />

6. Appendix: The Renaissance Platonists<br />

After the closing of the <strong>Neo</strong>-platonic Academy in Athens by the Emperor Justinian in 529 CE,<br />

<strong>Platonism</strong> ceased to be a living philosophy. Due to the efforts of the Christian philosopher Boethius<br />

(480-525 CE), who translated Porphyry’s Isagoge, and composed numerous original works as well, the<br />

Middle Ages received a faint glimmer of the ancient glories of the Platonic philosophy. St. Augustine,<br />

also, was responsible for imparting a sense of <strong>Neo</strong>-platonic doctrine to the Latin West, but this was<br />

by way of commentary and critique, and not in any way a systematic exposition of the philosophy.<br />

Generally speaking, it is safe to say that the European Middle Ages remained in the grip of<br />

Aristotelianism until the early Renaissance, when certain brilliant Italian thinkers began to<br />

rediscover, translate, and expound upon the original texts of <strong>Platonism</strong>. Chief among these thinkers<br />

were Marsilio Ficino (1433-1492) and Pico Della Mirandola (1463-1494). Ficino produced fine Latin<br />

translations of Plato’s Dialogues, the Enneads of Plotinus, and numerous works by Porphyry,<br />

Iamblichus, Proclus, Pseudo-Dionysius, and many others. In addition to his scholarly ability, Ficino<br />

was also a fine commentator and philosopher in his own right. His brilliant essay on Five Questions<br />

Concerning The Mind is a concise summary of general <strong>Neo</strong>-platonic doctrine, based upon Ficino’s<br />

own view that the lot of the human soul is to inquire into its own nature, and that since this inquiry<br />

causes the human soul to experience misery, the soul must do everything it can to transcend the<br />

physical body and live a life worthy of the blessed angels (cf. Cassirer, et. al. (ed) 1948, p. 211-212).<br />

Giovanni Pico, the Count of Mirandola, was a colorful figure who lived a short life, fraught with<br />

strife. He aroused the ire of the papacy by composing a voluminous work defending nine-hundred<br />

theses drawn from his vast reading of the Ancients; thirteen of these theses were deemed heretical by<br />

the papacy, and yet Pico refused to change or withdraw a single one. Like his friend Ficino, Pico was<br />

a devotee of ancient wisdom, drawing not only upon the Platonic canon, but also upon the Pre-<br />

Socratic literature and the Hermetic Corpus, especially the Poimandres. Pico’s most famous work is<br />

the Oration on the Dignity of Man, in which he eloquently states his learned view that humankind<br />

was created by God “as a creature of indeterminate nature,” possessed of the unique ability to ascend<br />

or descend on the scale of Being through the autonomous exercise of free will (Oration 3, in Cassirer,<br />

et. al. (ed) 1948, p. 224). Pico’s view of free will was quite different from that expressed by Plotinus,<br />

and indeed most other <strong>Neo</strong>-Platonists, and it came as no surprise when Pico composed a treatise On<br />

Being and the One which ended on Aristotelian terms, declaring the One to be coincident with or<br />

persisting amidst Being — a wholly un-Platonic doctrine. With Ficino, then, we may say that<br />

<strong>Platonism</strong> achieved a brief moment of archaic glory, while with Pico, it was plunged once again into<br />

the quagmire of self-referential empiricism.<br />

7. References<br />

• Cassirer, Ernst; Kristeller, Paul Oskar; Randall, John Herman Jr. (editors) The Renaissance Philosophy of Man<br />

(University of Chicago Press 1948).<br />

• Cooper, John M. (ed.), Plato: Complete Works (Hackett Publishing 1997).<br />

• Copleston S.J., Frederick, A History of Philosophy (vol. I, part II): Greece and Rome (Image Books 1962).<br />

• Dillon, John (1977), The Middle Platonists (Cornell University Press).<br />

• Eusebius (tr. G.A. Williamson 1965), The History of the Church (Penguin Books).<br />

• Fowden, Garth, The Egyptian Hermes: A Historical Approach To The Late Pagan Mind (Cambridge University Press<br />

1986).<br />

• Hadot, Pierre (tr. M. Chase), Plotinus, or The Simplicity of Vision (University of Chicago Press 1993).<br />

• Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (tr. E.S. Haldane and Frances H. Simson), Lectures on the History of Philosophy (vol.<br />

II): Plato And The Platonists (Bison Books 1995).<br />

• Jaeger, Werner, Early Christianity and Greek Paideia (Harvard University Press 1961).<br />

• Layton, Bentley (1987), The Gnostic Scriptures (Doubleday: The Anchor Bible Reference Library).<br />

• O’Brien S.J., <strong>El</strong>mer (1964), The Essential Plotinus: Representative Treatises From The Enneads (Hackett Publishing).


• Origen of Alexandria, Commentary on John, tr. in The Ante-Nicene Fathers, vol. X. (Eerdmans 1979, reprint).<br />

• Origen of Alexandria, On First Principles [De Principiis], tr. in The Ante-Nicene Fathers, vol. IV. (Eerdmans 1979,<br />

reprint).<br />

• Philo of Alexandria (tr. F.H. Colson and G.H. Whitaker), On the Creation of the World [De Opificio Mundi], in vol. 1 of<br />

The Loeb Classical Library edition of Philo (Harvard University Press 1929).<br />

• Plotinus (tr. A.H. Armstrong), The Enneads, in seven volumes (Loeb Classical Library: Harvard University Press<br />

1966).<br />

• Porphyry (tr. K. Guthrie), Launching-Points to the Realm of Mind [Pros ta noeta aphorismoi] (Phanes Press 1988).<br />

• Porphyry (tr. A. Zimmern), Porphyry’s Letter to His Wife Marcella Concerning the Life of Philosophy and the Ascent<br />

to the Gods (Phanes Press 1986).<br />

• Porphyry (tr. A.H. Armstrong), Life of Plotinus [Vita Plotini], in volume one of the Loeb Classical Library edition of<br />

Plotinus (Harvard University Press 1966).<br />

• Proclus (tr. T. Taylor), Lost Fragments of Proclus (Wizards Bookshelf 1988).<br />

• Proclus (tr. T. Taylor), Ten Doubts Concerning Providence, and On the Subsistence of Evil (Ares Publishers 1980).<br />

• Pseudo-Dionysius (tr. C. Luibheid 1987), Pseudo-Dionysius: The Complete Works (Paulist Press).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!