Academia.eduAcademia.edu
1 MARIA DE LOURDES BACHA REALISM AND TRUTH – PEIRCE´S THEMES Discussion paper mlbacha@gmail.com 2014 2 To Ana and Júlio 3 I would like to thank my friends, who have helped with suggestions, ideas, and hard work: Jorgina Santos, Ligia Feitosa; my colleagues from Peirce Edition Project, Professors Nathan Houser, Andre DeTienne, Cornelis de Waal for the kidness with which they welcomed me; Professor Lúcia Santaella, PhD, for supporting the post doctoral project; my friend Júlio Lamounier, for providing financial support to publish this book. 4 Summary Introduction ............................................................................................. 005 Part I In defense of Scientific Realism .................................................. 008 1. Realism and antirealism ........................................................................ 009 2. Peircean realism ................................................................................... 023 Part II Would the Truth be the best goal for scientific inquiry? .......... 051 1. Categorization of theories of truth ......................................................... 052 2. Peirce and the theory of truth: correspondence or convergence?......... 060 2.1 Truth and method .......................................................................... 079 2.2 Truth and pragmatismo ................................................................. 090 Final considerations ............................................................................... 098 References ............................................................................................... 100 List of Tables Table 1 New Realism and Idealism ....................................................................... 022 Table 2 Categorization of theories of truth ............................................................ 057 List of figures Figure 1 Theories of Truth ..................................................................................... 059 5 INTRODUCTION This work may be regarded as the continuation of two previous papers that have been published: the first named C. S. Peirce´s Theory of Inquiry and the second The Induction from Aristotle to Peirce. In C. S. Peirce´s Theory of Inquiry, we aimed at showing that for Peirce the inquiry starts from an uncomfortable state of doubt, which blocks the flow of usual actions and makes it difficult to choose among alternative courses of action. This is a real, genuine doubt, and not just a methodological doubt, a make-believe. Thus, the scientific inquiry constitutes an effort to put an end to the doubt and reestablish a state of belief in which the truth would then be a belief unshakeable by the doubt. The Theory of Inquiry can also be called The Theory of Scientific Method. According to Peirce, only the scientific method can lead us to the truth, in the long run, in a long way, which constitutes the dynamics process of inquiry. This process is subject to both error and chance, but it can be self-corrected. Agreement of opinions is the sole objective of the inquiry process, which comprises three stages: abduction, deduction, and induction. The Theory of Inquiry is grounded in this distinction, which formalizes a cycle: abduction, deduction, induction, new abduction. Due to the researches on the theory of inquiry, our attention has been drawn to induction, resulting in the second publication: The Induction from Aristotle to Peirce, which aims at analyzing the role of realism in the formulation of his theory of induction, reminding that, in Peirce, the validity of induction derives from the realistic environment of his philosophy. In Peirce, the foundation of induction is the realism of the continua or the doctrine of synechism in contrast with the normalistic, deterministic and necessitarian view of other authors, especially Mill. Therefore, the approach to this topic escapes from the purely logical focus, using Peirce´s theory of reality as ground for the inductive argument. In view of the interest in Peirce´s work and as a result of the postdoctoral research, the paper Realism and Truth – Peirce´s themes is now being presented. It aims at analyzing these two key topics for understanding 6 his work, mainly his methodeutic. This book focuses on the discussion about Charles Sanders Peirce´s realistic conception of truth. Charles Sanders Peirce was born in Cambridge, Massachusetts, in 1839. Son of a famous Harvard mathematician, he graduated in Science and received his PhD in Chemistry. He taught Logic at John Hopkins University and worked as a scientist at the U.S. Coast and Geodetic Survey until 1891. He died in 1914, in Arisbe, at the age of 75. He had cancer, and died poor and isolated, working on his manuscripts and virtually unknown. Peirce has carried out scientific researches that contain many important contributions not only to mathematical logic, but also astronomy, photometry, geodesy, psychophysics, and philology. His work with pendulums was internationally recognized, and this work with measurements together with studies on the theory of probable error had great influence on the growth of some aspects of his philosophy, especially his doctrine of chance and continuity. Being both an accurate thinker and familiar with the actual process our knowledge on the laws of nature is built, Peirce was against the claim that experience would lead to absolute evidence, because one cannot disregard discrepancies due to errors of observation. His philosophy seeks harmonious answers to a number of questions, such as the status of cosmos, the matter of temporality, the matter of knowledge, the matter of belief and doubt, the matter of inwardness and outwardness, the subject-object dichotomy, the possible conditions of thought, real, and imaginary. As a figure of the 19th century, it is no surprise that some issues such as indeterminism, uncertainty or complexity are part of his work. Peirce has brought the spirit of scientific inquiry to Philosophy, assuming that philosophical subjects are or may become scientific issues. For this reason, with proper adaptations, he has proposed applying to Philosophy the observation methods, hypothesis and experiments used by science. For Peirce, the path to Philosophy should be pursued through the logic of science. Therefore, as a scientist, he was primarily interested in the logic of science, and understanding the logic of science meant understanding reasoning methods. Taking into account that there is no thought or 7 reasoning without signs, Semiotics, as the study of all possible kinds of signs, emerged as a natural consequence of Peircean discoveries about Logic. Even though Peirce considered each and every human production, achievement and expression a semiotic issue, Semiotics or Logic is just part of his philosophical set, which, in turn, is also part of a larger system, which can be perceived by analyzing the classification of sciences chart. According to Peirce, Logic is the science of what must be and what should be true representation; to sum up, it is the philosophy of representation. Thus, the theme Truth is associated with Logic, Reasoning, and especially scientific method, and cannot be detached from Realism, which is a metaphysical hypothesis, but Metaphysics as the science of reality. Part I is entitled In defense of Scientific Realism and aims at analyzing the debate on scientific realism at the end of 20th century and early 21st century. At first, it is presented a literature review on the realismantirealism debate, and then the text presents a discussion on the assumptions of Peirce's realism. Regarding Part II, entitled Would the Truth be the best goal for scientific inquiry?, it starts with an overview of several projects on the theories of truth aiming at contextualizing Peirce´s theory of truth. 8 PARTE I IN DEFENSE OF SCIENTIFIC REALISM This doctrine is as follows:—Everything in the world belongs to some natural class or real kind. The difference between an artificial class and a natural class or real kind lies in this: that the things which belong to an artificial class have but a few points of resemblance, whereas the things that compose a natural class resemble one another in innumerable respects. […] Horse is a natural class; red horse is not. Yet the members of the latter class resemble each other in one more respect than do the members of the former class. The true difference seems to be this: Red horses have nothing whatever in common except what all horses have in common together with what all red things have in common; whereas it would be impossible so to define horses, that the definition itself should imply all that horses have in common (W1:417) . 9 1. REALISM AND ANTIREALISM The conflict between realism and anti-realism is a conflict about the kind of meaning possessed by statements of the disputed class. For the anti-realist, an understanding of such a statement consists in knowing what counts as evidence adequate for the assertion of the statement, and the truth of the statement can consist only in the existence of such evidence. For the realist, the notion of truth plays a more crucial role in the manner of determining the meaning of the statement (Dummett, 1978 155.) The questions [ ] whether there is any form of realism or antirealism that would call for a particular theory of truth, and whether there is any conception of truth with distinctive implications in the realism debate? And the answer to both questions has turned out to be no. (Horwich, 1996:197) This topic aims at analyzing the debate on scientific realism at the end of 20th century and early 21st century. At first, it is presented a literature review on the realism and antirealism debate, and then the text presents a discussion on the assumptions of Peirce's realism. The review of literature shows that researches on the nature and the conditions and extent of human knowledge are some of the most persistent and intriguing problems of philosophy and epistemology. These problems derive from a reflection on the world around us, generating controversies over skepticism, rationalism, externalism, foundationalism. Some skeptics defend the argument that we have no justified beliefs about certain classes of propositions, and thus, would not have reasons to believe propositions about the physical world. Thus, regarding Descartes’ question (what do I really know about the external world?), skeptics’ answers are pessimistic. 10 Since our knowledge of the external world comes from our senses, how can we know anything about the world without first prove that our senses are reliable? Or, how can we gain knowledge using a source of beliefs without first showing that it is reliable? Or, has the debate run out of steam? In discussions on scientific realism, what is striking is the absence of consensus on the principles that constitute a realistic view of the natural sciences, mainly because scientific advances have transformed the way of thinking about the world: Nature is no longer taken to be as our senses indicate it to be. Entities and mechanisms invisible to the naked eye, such as electromagnetic waves, electrons, proctons, neutrinos and DNA molecules – to mention but a few-are said to populate the world and cause the observable phenomena (PSILLOS, 1999: xvii). Thus, there are other questions: why should we consider scientific theories true or approximately true, or why should we believe that these entities postulated by our best theories are real? Why not consider such theories nothing more than instruments for systematization? (PSILLOS, 1999: xvii). On one hand, what about the theoretical entities (T-entities)? On the other hand, can we consider the relations shown in mathematics real? According to Peirce´s arguments, mathematics builds its objects in the form of hypotheses, and from them draws the necessary conclusions, without dealing with matters of fact: Mathematics is engaged solely in tracing out the consequences of hypotheses, and never considers whether or not anything be existentially true, or not. (CP 1.247) The necessary reasoning of mathematics is performed by means of observation and experiment (CP 3.560) But the mathematician observes nothing but the diagrams he himself constructs; and no occult compulsion governs his hypotheses except one from the depths of mind itself. Thus the distinguishing 11 characteristic of mathematics is that it is the scientific study of hypotheses which it first frames and then traces to their consequences (NEM IV:268). According to Rorty (1967: 2), the discussion shifted from the question whether the material reality is mind-dependent to one about what kind of true assertions are there in the representational relations to non-linguistic items? For the author, a discussion on realism would only center on whether assertions of physics can match the "facts of the matter", or if the assertions of mathematics and ethics can also have this possibility. The Philosophers [..] seem fated to end the Century discussing the same topic –realism- which they were discussing in 1900. In that year the opposite of realism was still idealism. But now language has replaced mind as that which, supposedly, stands over “reeality” […] Nowadays the opposite of realism is called simply “antirealism” (Rorty, 1967:2). Psillos (2001:xx), on “Scientific Realism – How science tracks truth”, argues that there is an endless battlefield of controversies regarding realism, including the following: • whether science can possibly describe a mind-independent world? • whether science can go beyond whatever can be observed by the naked eye and reveal truths about unobservable causes of the phenomena? • how exactly scientific theories should be understood? • whether one needs to accept the truth of scientific theories in order to account for the success of science and for salient features of its practice? Also according to Psillos (1999), the debate on scientific realism evolved from the discussion on linguistic terms, that is, about the meaning of scientific discourse or about whether scientific terms denote something to the argument over the power of scientific theories to explain unobservable entities. Fine (1991: 261) declared: 12 Realism is dead. Its death was announced by the neopositivists who realized that they could accept all the results of science, including all the members of the scientific zoo […] Recent philosophical argument in support of realism tries to move from the success of the scientific enterprise to the necessity for a realist account of its practice (Fine, 1991: 261). Boyd (1991) argued: The positive evidence for scientific realism thus rests primarily on features of scientific practice which would be discernible even if one limited one's examination to very recent science. According to the realist, realism provides the only acceptable explanation for the current instrumental reliability of scientific methodology in mature sciences. Realism does however entail interesting conclusions about historical development within mature sciences – that is, within those sciences in which theorethical considerations contribute significantly to a high level of instrumental reliability of method (Boyd, 1991:221). What could constitute a realistic view of science? To Plastino (1995: 14), the following statements could clarify this issue: • he existence and nature of the facts of the world do not depend on theories or methods that science uses. • All scientific assertion, when literally interpreted, is either true or false. • The truth-value of a scientific assertion is determined by the world. An assertion is true when it maintains a corresponding relationship with the world. • Science seeks theories that make a true (or approximately true) description of the world. • The theoretical terms remain the same during scientific changes. New scientific findings absorb the core of preceding ones. • The progress of science consists of a convergent process of approaching a complete and true scientific theory. 13 • In mature sciences, theories are approximately true and their core terms refer to objects of the world. It can be argued that there are several ways of approaching scientific realism. Some of them consist of metaphysical assumptions (ontological) on the existence and independence of the outer physical world others focus on epistemological aspects of scientific research of the world or semantic aspects of the interpretation of scientific theories. However, in most cases, scientific realism is described as a hybrid, integrated set of philosophical theses concerning different aspects and dimensions of science. The metaphysical stance asserts that the world has a definite and mind-independent natural-kind structure; the semantic stance takes scientific theories at face-value, seeing them as truthconditioned descriptions of their intended domain, both observable or unobservable […]. The epistemic stance regards mature and predictively successful scientific theories as well-confirmed and approximately true of the world. So, the entities posited by them, or at any rate, entities very similar to those posited, do inhabit the world (Psillos, 1999: xix). For Horwich (1996: 187-198), realism is common-sense. For realists there are facts of physics, mathematics, psychology, history, and so on. These facts typically do not owe their existence to our awareness of them-or even to the possibility of our becoming aware of them and we are, as it happens, able to acquire considerable knowledge in these domains. Thus the debate between realism and anti-realism is a dispute between business-as-usual and the philosophical revision of established belief and practice […]. The scientific anti-realist is someone who thinks that this combination of common-sense views is incoherent and untenable. He cannot see how it is possible for there to be theoretical facts that, on the one hand, are within the reach of our methods of conceptualization and investigation but, 14 on the other hand, exists independently of them. Thus, for a scientific anti-realist, the paradigm of knowledge is of observed facts, which are regarded as dependent upon human capacities (Horwich, 1996: 188-189). Bensusan (1994:37) presents three realistic theses. The first is the literalness thesis, that is, that the language of science deals with entities, either observable or not. This language consists of expressions that are mostly genuine statements and should be interpreted according to a theoretical model that involves entities other than mere human feelings and just ordinary observable entities. The second realistic thesis is unity, according to which theories that prevail over competing ones take into account justified and non-pragmatic criteria, they are the most suitable among the competing theories available. The third corresponds to ontological realism, which implies the principle that what exists does not depend on theories and representation. If accepted, these three theses can be connected with the idea of truth by correspondence, "which seems to be naturally suggested”. Putnam & Putnan (1990) discuss four types of realism: naive realism, metaphysical realism, internal realism and realism of common sense, which oppose each other. Naive realism cannot be confused with the realism of common sense because it boils down to the belief that the subject has to be in an absolute relationship with the world and that the real world consists of appearances that this subject can grasp. When it comes to metaphysical realism and external perspective, Putnam rejects there main points: that the world is a fixed totality of mind-independent objects, there is a single coherent and true description of the world and that truth implies some sort of correspondence. For internal realism, reference and truth do not depend on any mysterious relationship of correspondence, but they are both internal to the theories. For Putnam & Putnan (1990), any assumption that there are mindindependent entities does not make any sense. He proposes the abandonment of the traditional dichotomy between the world itself and the concepts we use to think and talk about it, and the truth. The reference of 15 our linguistic expressions is related to the conceptual scheme, that is, they are internal to the perspective adopted. Some orthodox formulations on scientific realism that have support in the theses described below: • there is a definite outer world (consisting of entities with properties and relations) that is largely independent of our knowledge or experience; • science seeks substantial and accurate information of the aspects of the world, that is, presenting true theories that represent the elements and the structure of the world; and • epistemic access to the world is possible and it is expected that the progressive development of science will improve our ability to obtain knowledge (at least approximately) of the world. Realism gives meaning to science through the postulation of the objective existence of the world (which does not depend on our cognitive capacity) and a conception of truth by correspondence. A scientific proposition is seen as true or false due to the way things are, regardless of our ability to access the world. In the realist view, the world is what the true proposition says it is, providing an external standard to which scientific theories must conform, because interactions are built from the interactions with the world. The legitimacy of scientific statements therefore rests in external relations maintained with their object of study, that is, in agreement (approximately) with some parts of reality. For Rorty (1980), scientific theories should be a mirror that reflects the structure of nature. In general, realists understand that the scientific enterprise aims at knowing the truth about the outer world and that the use of scientific methods and procedures may gradually lead to the discovery of truth and, as a consequence, to consensus of opinions. Regarding some specific true assertions, Rorty (1967: 2) claims that the term antirealism is ambiguous because it is the standard word that refers to the statement that there is no real issue these assertions could represent. In turn, Dummett (1978, 72) states that: Realism I characterize as the belief that statements of the disputed class possess an objective truth- 16 value, independently of our means of knowing it; they are true of false in virtue of a reality existing independently of us. n contrast: The anti-realist opposes to this the view that statements of the disputed class are tied directly to what we count as evidence for them, in such a way that a statement of this disputed class, if true at all, can be true only in virtue of something of which we could know and which we should count as evidence for its truth (DUMMETT, 1978 146). From the point of view of antirealism, Bensusan (1994:46) discusses three theses: Van Fraasen´s constructive empiricism, which defends the underdetermination of every theory, the instrumentalism which can be divided into pragmatic (each theory can be replaced by endless others) and epistemic (the theory may be a privileged and most suitable instrument to handle a specific field). Plastino (1995) argues that antirealists believe that scientific realism put an end to an unsustainable tension among their main thesis, that is, the conflict between "the metaphysical autonomy of the world (its independence from us) and its epistemic accessibility (our ability to learn something about it)". For antirealists, however, it is not possible to reconcile several ontological, semantic and epistemological assumptions that often make up scientific realism. Based on internal (and external) criticism, antirealists conclude that it is necessary to deeply change the traditional realistic image of science (Horwich, 1996:57). In order to do so, antirealists have many options: • • Some reject the assumption that certain types of objects exist, for example, one can deny the existence of unobservable objects (instrumentalism), so that it is not legitimate to literally believe in theories that approach them, or things in themselves independent of the mind or language (conceptual relativism). Others prefer to show that certain types of objects are reducible to others that seem to have epistemological priority (phenomenalism). 17 • • Others question our ability to know objects inaccessible to observation (constructive empiricism), although they do not deny the existence of unobservable entities. Besides, there are antirealists who propose other conceptions of truth and reference which eliminate the alleged internal conflict of scientific realism (Plastino, 1995: 15). However, taking into account an antirealist and instrumentalist view of science, the realistic principles are generally relegated or criticized, because the meaning of science is not the result of an attempt to represent a reality that exists independently of us, but "rather the pragmatic virtues of theories (such as their instrumental reliability)". [...] to argue for realism we must employ methods more stringent than those in ordinary scientific practice. In particular one must not beg the question as to the significance of explanatory hypotheses by assuming that they carry truth as well as explanatory efficacy (Fine, 1991: 263). The raison d'être of science would be in how it allows us to guide our actions and thoughts, and the main goal of scientific research is to build theories that, "to some extent, are appropriate to the phenomena of our observation and for extracting new and successful future consequences of events that we can perceive and investigate". Thus, a scientific theory is accepted provided that it works satisfactorily. Somehow, scientific practice is understood as an outward projection of us, our interests, habits and capabilities (Fine, 1991). For instrumentalists, it is within the scientific practice itself that the merits of scientific findings are recognized and appreciated, and therefore it is necessary that the strategies adopted by the scientific community are seen as able to perform or progressively lead to the expected results. In this context, the truth, as correspondence or agreement between theory and reality, should not be regarded as a goal of scientific research, because in general we do not know how to determine whether a given scientific hypothesis or theory has the property of being true or closer to the 18 truth than another. Although the truth may be rigorously defined and an attainable principle, there is no operational criteria ensuring that a statement or set of statements of empirical science may be true or asymptotically close to the truth (in realistic terms). Consequently, even in the face of a scientific truth, we would not identify or recognize it as such, and the best we can and should expect of scientific theories is agreement with our views, accuracy and simplicity (in many ways), power to predict and explain, ability to unify and systematize empirical laws, the scope of the field, effectiveness in solving theoretical problems, practical application, consistency with other well-established beliefs. (Plastino, 1995) […] the realistic notion of truth (as correspondence) transcends our knowledge in a way that there is no implication for the effective practice of the agents of scientific research (and, moreover, opens the doors to skepticism) (Plastino, 1995:16). The instrumentalist conception of science believes that the practical success of science does not allow the current belief in (literally interpreted) scientific theories or the existence of theoretical entities (unobservable) they postulate, and pragmatic considerations in favor of a scientific theory only seem to indicate that it is a useful tool. In this context, the so-called theoretical entities of science are regarded as fictions, mental constructs or simple and convenient idealizations to the purposes of science. For instrumentalists, the arguments used to justify the acceptance of scientific results are not basis for assuming that science is a source of reliable information about the "underlying structure" to observable natural phenomena. The contemporary debate realism versus instrumentalism focuses primarily on the epistemological question of whether the explanatory and predictive power of a scientific theory justifies the belief in the truth (or approximate truth) of this theory (Plastino, 1995). However, according to Plastino (1995:10), a historical analysis of the evolution of science also shows the inadequacy of realism based on its explanation for scientific success, because many scientific theories that had 19 considerable success in the past postulated theoretical entities whose existence today is denied (such as phlogiston, caloric fluid or vital forces). Without an explanation for the instrumental success of science, it would be necessary to recognize this success as the result of a "miracle" or perhaps a mysterious "cosmic coincidence" and realism could be presented as the idea that offers the best explanation for the experimental success of science. But, as Fine points out (1991), there would be a "manifest circularity in this attempt to justify the realist view" and one should expect that the reasoning of scientific realism would involve "methods more rigorous than those used in ordinary scientific practice". Thus, realists are not able to show (without begging the question) that the explanatory power of realism ensures the belief in the truth (approximately) of theory or the existence of theoretical entities it postulates. This deficiency in the miracle argument is rightly recognized by realists like Boyd (1990), to whom the acceptance of a realistic explanation as a scientific theory does not imply accepting scientific realism, because a realistic explanation can be interpreted in a non-realistic way. Thus, in order to avoid circularity, scientific realism should be included in a larger philosophical package of epistemological, metaphysical and semantic theses, including the naturalized version of knowledge and reference, in which philosophical considerations and scientific discoveries are closely related. The argumentative strategy to be used will be to show the superiority of this realistic package before any other rival philosophical package (Boyd, 1991). Plastino (1995) explains that in order to accept a realist´s explanation, without compromising with the truth of realistic theses, an instrumentalist should only admit its effectiveness to satisfactorily explain certain types of phenomena. Thus, the instrumentalist proposes that the realist conception of truth is replaced by a pragmatist conception in which truth is analyzed in terms of instrumental reliability (or Dewey´s "guaranteed assertability"). 20 But the defense of realism must take into account the existence of entities that are considered unnecessary by some antirealist positions such as phenomenalism, or nominalism (as abstract ideas or mathematical objects), and that many are willing to remove with A scientific man must be an Ockham´s razor. For Bensusan (1994:37), realism must reject an instrumentalist view of theories and argue that science deals with entities and properties of these entities, whether observable or not, and its language seems to not only treat these entities and their properties. single-minded and sincere with himself. Otherwise, his love of truth will melt away, at once. He can, therefore, hardly be otherwise than an honest , fair-minded man. True, a few naturalists have been accused of purloining specimens; and some men have been far from judicial in advocating their theories. Both of these faults must be exceedingly deleterious to their scientific ability. But on the whole, scientific men have been the best of men. It is quite natural, therefore, that a young man who might develope into a scientific man should be a well-conducted person (CP 1.49). However, for those who defend "language games", "ontological relativism," "extreme translation" and "views of the world" as Wittgenstein, Quine and Goodman, knowledge is not an immediate mirroring of external things, but the construction of "narratives" and "interpretations", which are, in turn, systems of symbols ordering and categorizing experience. In this context, the linguistic-pragmatic-hermeneutic turn "would dissolve foundationalism, representationalism and transcendentalism" and the place of epistemology and metaphysics could be taken by "a world without substances or essences" or "truth without correspondence to reality". For foundationalists, beliefs about "sense data" and the present experience are infallible, then they can play the role assigned to them in this form of empiricism; beliefs about our sensory states are infallible and can be justified when resorting to that foundation. Some philosophies presuppose a metaphysical or epistemological realism and share the idea that there is something objective enough to serve as a foundation to ensure the rational argument or possible conclusions about the most intelligible perspectives on the experience or the world. 21 Others refute the idea of a "broader perspective", a "metavocabulary", "common space", "neutral scheme" or "god's eye-view". Opposition to the metaphysical tradition may take a number of forms. For philosophers like Rorty, Davidson and Putnam, the core issue of philosophy - external reality - can be resolved neither by antirealism nor by phenomenalism. Rorty (1989: xiii-xiv) claims that traditional philosophical guidelines assume a neutral and comprehensive view of reality, which can be based on criteria of truth and appropriateness. Davidson (1990:309) sees no reason to suppose that realism and antirealism, understood in terms of radical non-epistemic or epistemic character or truth, are the only ways of giving substance to a theory of truth or meaning. From another perspective, Hildebrand (2003:10) considers two movements which succeeded to realism: at the turn of the 20th century, some philosophers (like Moore, Mach, Peirce, James and Dewey) rose against idealism, amazed by advances in biology, mathematics and logic. These realists emphasized the independence of objects and their relationships. Later on, Perry and Montague became well-known as representatives of New Realism. The New Realism had a great impact and the rebellion against idealism not only ensured the relative independence of the object, but also involved a redefinition of the mind itself. However, the New Realism has been unable to assess awareness and the problem of error, being replaced by a movement called Critical Realism, which argued that the knowing mind needed to be mediated by some kind of non-physical interface. The epistemological distinction between object and vehicle of knowledge becomes crucial for Critical Realists. Critical Realism would have opened a gap between New Realism and Pragmatism. The chart below summarizes these considerations: 22 Table 1 - New realists and Idealists Issue “Mind” includes or characterizes New Realists nothing intrinsecally its own’, mind is a relation between nonmental contents (contra Descartes’ mind-as container model). Mind’s powers vis-a-vis are nil; mind observes its objetct but does not alter its objetcts Knower-known knowledge is na external relationship relation; the beinf of objetcts does not depend on the subject Mind’s essence mind is relational, not substantive; mental states does not depend on the subject Mind’s ontological status mind does not exist apart from things, events or entities in relation; they however, do not depend upon mind Source: Hildebrand (2003, p.12) Idealists all reality are criative and constitutive object cannot be causally severed from knowing subjetc mind is a systematic unity, a self-evolving universal mind exists independently of objects though it may be influenced by them 23 2. PEIRCEAN REALISM The successes of modern science ought to convince us that induction is the only capable imperator of truth-seeking. Now pragmaticism is simply the doctrine that the inductive method is the only essential to the ascertainment of the intellectual purport of any symbol (CP 8.209,1905). Taking into account a Peircean perspective, the following pages are an attempt to respond to the claims that metaphysical statements about reality, extralinguistic objects, or even systematic speculations are possible, and do not constitute meaningless, futile or out of fashion issues, as some of the opponents say about scientific realism. From an epistemological view, Peirce was aware of the need to provide both a justification for the belief in the existence of an external world and a criterion for determining which objects of our experience belong to the class of external objects. And Peirce asks: "How do I know they are real?" The answer lies in the following considerations: • • • • “If investigation cannot be regarded as proving that there are Real things, it at least does not lead to a contrary conclusion; but the method and the conception on which it is based remain ever in harmony. No doubts of the method, therefore, necessarily arise from its practice, as is the case with all the others. The feeling which gives rise to any method of fixing belief is a dissatisfaction at two repugnant propositions. But here already is a vague concession that there is some one thing which a proposition should represent. Nobody, therefore, can really doubt that there are Reals, for, if he did, doubt would not be a source of dissatisfaction. The hypothesis, therefore, is one which every mind admits. So that the social impulse does not cause men to doubt it. Everybody uses the scientific method about a great many things, and only ceases to use it when he does not know how to apply it. Experience of the method has not led us to doubt it, but, on the contrary, scientific investigation has had the most wonderful triumphs in 24 the way of settling opinion. These afford the explanation of my not doubting the method or the hypothesis which it supposes; and not having any doubt, nor believing that anybody else whom I could influence has, it would be the merest babble for me to say more about it. If there be anybody with a living doubt upon the subject, let him consider it” (CP 5.384, 1877). But if there was not an object, if there was not a real object, there would not be truth and for Peirce we can only say that there is such a thing as the truth because otherwise the reasoning and thinking would not be valuable. What do you mean by there being such a thing as Truth? You mean that something is SO—is correct, or just—whether you, or I, or anybody thinks it is so or not. Most persons, no doubt, opine that for every question susceptible of being answered by yes or no, one of these answers is true and the other false. (CP 2.135, 1902) For Peirce, the problem of knowledge of reality is based on the field of metaphysics. Then there would be at least two alternative positions: a priori and the empiricist or naturalist. The Kantian a priori position assumes that metaphysics is a science of pure reason, whose knowledge derives exclusively from concepts that are not influenced by any experience. The empiricist assumes that "this question is a question of fact, and experience alone can settle it" (CP 2.137, 1902). In 1887, in "How to Make Our Ideas Clear", when formulating and defending rules of clarity about content, hypothesis and concepts, Peirce reaffirms realism, claiming that there is a real that will imposed itself even if we make mistakes and have totally misleading collective beliefs, because it does not matter what we think of it or the representations we make of it; continuous and independent, “reality does not necessarily depend on thinking in general, but only on what you or a definite number of people think about it" (CP 5.408, 1877). Real establishes beliefs and therefore the representation we make of it is not arbitrary, hence deriving the concept of truth and "the opinion which 25 is fated to be ultimately agreed to by all who investigate, is what we mean by the truth, and the object represented in this opinion is the real” (CP 5.407, 1877). The inquiry that reinforces this belief has a telos, which Peirce calls fate, which is an activity of thinking "by which we are carried, not where we wish, but to a fore-ordained goal, is like the operation of destiny ". There is no way to escape the predestined opinion, no change in the point of view, no choice of other facts to be studied, not even a natural tendency of the spirit, this great hope is present in the concepts of truth and reality (CP 5.407, 1897) . But, by fate, one can also understand the consolidation of researchers’ opinion which is bound to meet the real. Peirce emphasizes the role of experience, that is, the experience is that belief or cognition imposed on someone through the course of his life. But how exactly does experience happen? Through a number of surprises (CP 5:51, 1905). One can lie about this, but no one can escape the fact that some things are forced upon their cognition (CP 2.138, 1902): Experience is that determination of belief and cognition generally which the course of life has forced upon a man. One may lie about it; but one cannot escape the fact that some things are forced upon his cognition. There is the element of brute force, existing whether you opine it exists or not. Somebody may object that if he did not think so, he would not be forced to think so; so that it is not an instance in point. But this is a double confusion of ideas. For in the first place, that something is, even if you think otherwise, is not disproved but demonstrated if you cannot think otherwise; and in the next place, what experience forces a man to think, of course he must think. But he is not therein forced to think that it is force that makes him think so. The very opinion entertained by those who deny that there is any Truth, in the sense defined, is that it is not force, but their inward freedom which determines their experiential cognition. But this 26 opinion is flatly contradicted by their own experience. (CP 2.138, 1902). Even though some people insist on closing their eyes to the element of compulsion, they experience it directly. But the fact that it can be denied confirms the idea that it does not depend on the opinion one can have about it. The key hypothesis about the method of science is that there are reals, whose characters are entirely independent of our opinions about them. According to Peirce, the above arguments show that science not only legitimately admits the existence of an independent world but also needs to create it, in case it wants to keep the current, objective view of science. The hypothesis of Reality is the only evidence of the research method, "scientific investigation has had the most wonderful triumphs in the way of settling opinion” (CP 5.384, 1877). At any moment we are in possession of certain information, that is, of cognitions which have been logically derived by induction and hypothesis from previous cognitions which are less general, less distinct, and of which we have a less lively consciousness. These in their turn have been derived from others still less general, less distinct, and less vivid; and so on back to the ideal first, which is quite singular, and quite out of consciousness. This ideal first is the particular thing -in -itself. It does not exist as such. That is, there is nothing which is in -itself in the sense of not being relative to the mind, though things which are relative to the mind doubtless are, apart from that relation. That is, there is no thing which is in-itself in the sense of not being relative to the mind, though things which are relative to the mind doubtless are, apart from that relation. The cognitions which thus reach us by this infinite series of inductions and hypotheses (which though infinite a parte ante logice, is yet as one continuous process not without 27 a beginning in time) are of two kinds, the true and the untrue, or cognitions whose objects are real and those whose objects are unreal (CP 5.311, 1868). Thus, there are two types of cognitions that are found in this endless series of inductions and hypotheses - true or false, or cognitions whose objects are real and those whose objects are not real. The real is defined in the following passage: The real, then, is that which, sooner or later, information and reasoning would finally result in, and which is therefore independent of the vagaries of me and you. Thus, the very origin of the conception of reality shows that this conception essentially involves the notion of a COMMUNITY, without definite limits, and capable of a definite increase of knowledge. And so those two series of cognition — the real and the unreal — consist of those which, at a time sufficiently future, the community will always continue to re-affirm; and of those which, under the same conditions, will ever after be denied (CP 5.311, 1868). On the other hand, the existence of the real is followed by a final response to every question. Thus, all these arguments show a well-built defense of what is meant by true regarding the objectivity of knowledge about external reality. The real is not, therefore, per se an immediate object of thought, even though my thought may happen to coincide with it. Yet the real must influence thought or I could not by following any rules of reasoning arrive at any truth (W3:60). The fact that “the real is that which is not whatever we happen to think it, but is unaffected by what we may think of it” (CP 8.12, 1871); the fact that “there is an external reality independent of how you or I think” (CP 5.405,1877); the fact that “scientists may at first obtain different results, but, as each perfects his method and his processes, the results are found to move steadily together toward a destined centre. So with all scientific 28 research. Different minds may set out with the most antagonistic views, but the progress of investigation carries them by a force outside of themselves to one and the same conclusion” (CP 5 407, 1877), three ideas emerge: • reality does not depend on what is being thought and represented. • reality is essencially related to thinking and ideas. • the idea of reality is the end result of inquiry. In this context, Peirce assumes that: Suppose our opinion with reference to a given question to be quite settled, so that inquiry, no matter how far pushed, has no surprises for us on this point. Then we may be said to have attained perfect knowledge about that question. True, it is conceivable that somebody else should attain to a like "perfect knowledge," which should conflict with ours. He might know something to be white, which we should know was black. This is conceivable; but it is not possible, considering the social nature of man, if we two are ever to compare notes; and if we never do compare notes, and no third party talks with both and makes the comparison, it is difficult to see what meaning there is in saying we disagree. When we come to study the principle of continuity we shall gain a more ontological conception of knowledge and of reality; but even that will not shake the definition we now give. (CP 4.62, 1843) For Peirce, reality cannot be separated from its representations, that is, mental phenomena. Logic or semiotics is the only way not to fall into Locke´s “mentalism”, because our mental products are all signs and we cannot think without signs. This idea of reality is discussed in the following passage: There are Real things, whose characters are entirely independent of our opinions about them; those Reals affect our senses according to regular laws, and, 29 though our sensations are as different as are our relations to the objects, yet, by taking advantage of the laws of perception, we can ascertain by reasoning how things really and truly are; and any man, if he have sufficient experience and he reason enough about it, will be led to the one True conclusion. The new conception here involved is that of Reality. It may be asked how I know that there are any Reals. If this hypothesis is the sole support of my method of inquiry, my method of inquiry must not be used to support my hypothesis (CP 5.384, 1877). • • • • The reality of things is subject to the following properties: It does not depend on desire or opinion of individuals or groups of people; Consensus will be reached among people who have enough experience and carry out researches in the correct way; In fact, this consensus is not restricted to a specific community, but it may include any reasonable agent; Consensus results from the action of external reality on our senses and opinions. For Peirce, the idea of reality presents two important aspects: otherness, which represents the element that reacts (associated with Secondness, category of existence) and the insistence of brute force, that by maintaining certain regularity, enables knowledge (associated with Thirdness, that is the general category, the law), or in the words of Peirce: Although in all direct experience of reaction, an ego, a something within, is one member of the pair, yet we attribute reactions to objects outside of us. When we say that a thing exists, what we mean is that it reacts upon other things. That we are transferring to it our direct experience of reaction is shown by our saying that one thing acts upon another. It is our hypothesis to explain the phenomena, — a hypothesis, which like the working hypothesis of a scientific inquiry, we may not believe to be altogether 30 true, but which is useful in enabling us to conceive of what takes place (CP 7.534 s.d.). This study also emphasizes Peirce's view of Secondness category, showing that the compulsiveness of our perceptual experience ensures the externality of the object we perceive. Secondness is an experience that results from the reaction between ego and non-ego. The practical exigencies of life render Secondness the most prominent of the three. This is not a conception, nor is it a peculiar quality. It is an experience. It comes out most fully in the shock of reaction between ego and non-ego. It is there the double consciousness of effort and resistance. That is something which cannot properly be conceived. For to conceive it is to generalize it; and to generalize it is to miss altogether the hereness and nowness which is its essence. According to me, the idea of a reaction is not the idea of two plus forcefulness. On the contrary to think of two dots as two is to have a little experience of reaction and then to tell ourselves that that is to be taken only in a Pickwickian sense, as a mere reaction within the world of ideas, the experience of reaction itself at once leading us to think of a world of seconds or existences and a world of mere tame ideas; the one resistant, the other subject to our wills. We also find ourselves thinking of the things without us, as acting on one another, as really connected. Now it is your business as a psychologist to say how that comes about, not mine. I merely look at the phenomenon, and say that all idea of real relation, or connection, has in it that same element of irrational reaction. All the actual character of consciousness is merely the sense of the shock of the non-ego upon us (CP 8.266, 1903). Despite all his interest in signs, it was only in 1907 (PC 5461-496) that Peirce established the importance of semiotics to pragmatism, and the statement that all thoughts are signs becomes a realistic position. How can 31 an object internal to cognition represent an object external to our cognition? To resolve this issue it is necessary to analyze both Phenomenology and Peirce´s theory of perception. Starting with the Phenomenology, what does Peirce mean by phenomenon? How can we know that what presents itself to cognition is also a representation of a real object that is out of cognition. Peirce responds to this with the definition of the phenomenon: “I use the word phaneron to mean all that is present to the mind in any sense or in any way whatsoever, regardless of whether it be fact or figment” (CP 8.213). Experience is a cognitive process of signs, which corresponds to the category of Thirdness, but the most prominent element of this Thirdness process is its referential relations as well as Secondness’, which are expressed in the experience of dual reaction in our cognitive mind, and in this duality the objects represented are recognized. For science, facts cannot be seen in an atomic and unrelated way, they should be amenable to generalization, should be seen within a system, related and grouped according to general laws, because a true continuum cannot be exhausted by any multitude of individuals. True generality is in fact continuity. Or if the force of experience were mere blind compulsion, and we were utter foreigners in the world, then again we might as well think to please ourselves; because we then never could make our thoughts conform to that mere Secondness. But the saving truth is that there is a Thirdness in experience, an element of Reasonableness to which we can train our own reason to conform more and more. If this were not the case, there could be no such thing as logical goodness or badness; and therefore we need not wait until it is proved that there is a reason operative in experience to which our own can approximate. We should at once hope that it is so, since in that hope lies the only possibility of any knowledge (CP 5.160, 1903). However, realism is not just about the reality of the external world, it 32 can also be summed up in a question asked by Peirce in "Logic of 1873", that is, are there realities, “which are not only independent of my thought, your thought and anybody else´s thought, but in fact independent of thought altogether?”. And the answer to this question lies within the idea of final opinion: The objective final opinion is independent of the thoughts of any particular men, but is not independent of thought in general. That is to say, if there were no thought, there would be no opinion, and therefore, no final opinion (CP 7.336, 1873). At the heart of this question there is another one: whether generality, rationality, the being of laws or Thirdness are real.If they are not real, the world does not show any intelligible structure, the universe will not be revealed in the course of scientific research, but rather, it will present itself like a puzzle to which we will give orders. But if they are real, then there is a possibility of discovering the order and rationality of the universe, "a fragment of divine thought," knowing the intentions of the "divine geometer". Taking into account many aspects, for Peirce, the nominalist position is inconsistent. The first aspect claims that qualities are not real, unless they are really perceived. But what is quality? A quality is a mere abstract potentiality. For nominalists, what is potential or possible is nothing except what the present does, but for Peirce “quality only exists when it actually inheres in a body”, or “quality is the monadic element of the world” (CP 1.422–26, 1896), meaning that the idea of quality comprises suchness, unity and the reality of Firstness. The second aspect to be considered is related to the fact that percepts are subject to certain laws. For Peirce, if percepts were not a matter of law, our ideas would be a matter for indifference. It may be appropriate to think and act according to the law, but a set of rules would properly be superior to another. Whether all this be true or not, it must at any rate be admitted by every candid man that he does believe firmly and without doubt that to some extent phenomena are regular, that is, are governed by 33 general ideas; and so far as they are so, they are capable of prediction by reasoning. (CP 2.149, 1902). The third aspect concerns the reality of the possible. For nominalists, a possible is simply a function of our ignorance when making assumptions, but for Peirce it is not a matter of ignorance since nothing is involved except pure hypothesis. Nominalists consider Aristotle´s future contingent events a completely absurd, a particular event that will happen or not. There is nothing now in existence to constitute the truth of its being about to happen, or of its being about not to happen, unless it be certain circumstances to which only a law or uniformity can lend efficacy. But that law or uniformity, the nominalists say, has no real being; it is only a mental representation. If so, neither the being about to happen nor the being about not to happen has any reality at present; and the most that we can say is that the disjunction is true, but neither of the alternatives. If, however, we admit that the law has a real being, not of the mode of being of an individual, but even more real, then the future necessary consequent of a present state of things is as real and true as that present state of things itself (CP 6.367368, 1898). There is a fourth aspect: for nominalists, there is no connection between individual things. A nominalist defines action as a notion of law or uniformity in contrast to what Peirce argues: “a law of nature left to itself would be quite analogous to a court without a sheriff." Suppose a law of nature, such as the law of gravity, remains mere uniformity, a mere formula establishing a relationship between terms - what in the world would induce a stone, which is neither a term nor a concept, but just a plain thing, to act in accordance with such uniformity? All the other stones may have done so and this stone too on other occasions, and it would break the uniformity for it not to do so now. But what to do? And there is no use talking to a stone, which is deaf and has no reason. 34 It is the same with the operations of nature. With overwhelming uniformity, in our past experience, direct and indirect, stones left free to fall have fallen. Thereupon two hypotheses only are open to us. Either 1. the uniformity with which those stones have fallen has been due to mere chance and affords no ground whatever, not the slightest for any expectation that the next stone that shall be let go will fall; or 2. the uniformity with which stones have fallen has been due to some active general principle, in which case it would be a strange coincidence that it should cease to act at the moment my prediction was based upon it. That position, gentlemen, will sustain criticism. It is irrefragable. Of course, every sane man will adopt the latter hypothesis. If he could doubt it in the case of the stone — which he can't — and I may as well drop the stone once for all — I told you so! — if anybody doubts this still, a thousand other such inductive predictions are getting verified every day, and he will have to suppose every one of them to be merely fortuitous in order reasonably to escape the conclusion that general principles are really operative in nature. That is the doctrine of scholastic realism. (CP 100-101). The nominalist would say that laws are merely general, formulas relating to mere terms. If realist, a law of nature will be regarded as a type of this in futuro, which has a present reality that consists on the fact that events will take place in accordance with the formulation of that law. I should ask the objector whether he was a nominalist or a scholastic realist. If he is a nominalist, he holds that laws are mere generals, that is, formulae relating to mere terms; and ordinary good sense ought to force him to acknowledge that there are real connections between individual things regardless of mere formulae. Now any real connection whatsoever between individual things 35 involves a reaction between them in the sense of this category. The objector may, however, take somewhat stronger ground by confessing himself to be a scholastic realist, holding that generals may be real. A law of nature, then, will be regarded by him as having a sort of esse in futuro. That is to say they will have a present reality which consists in the fact that events will happen according to the formulation of those laws. It would seem futile for me to attempt to reply that when, for example, I make a great effort to lift a heavy weight and perhaps am unable to stir it from the ground, there really is a struggle on this occasion regardless of what happens on other occasions; because the objector would simply admit that on such an occasion I have a quality of feeling which I call a feeling of effort, but he would urge that the only thing which makes this designation appropriate to the feeling is the regularity of connection between this feeling and certain motions of matter (CP 5.48, 1903). We have performed experiments with all three categories of cognition, but the elements of Secondness have more intensity and are the most vivid, because the practical demands of life render Secondness the most prominent. Secondness is neither a concept, nor a unique quality; it is an experience that manifests itself. The simplest characteristic, common to the second category, is the element of struggle. For Peirce, regarding the element of struggle, there is no difference between the agent and the patient. The result decides (CP 5.45, 1903). Secondness is what we experience when our will meets resistance, or when something imposes itself on our senses. Action and reaction are equal. If you find that the door is pushed open in spite of you, you will say that it was the person on the other side that acted and you that resisted, while if you succeed in pushing the door to, you will say that it was you who acted and the other person that resisted. In general, we call the one that succeeds by means of his effort the agent 36 and the one that fails the patient. But as far as the element of Struggle is concerned, there is no difference between being an agent and being a patient. It is the result that decides; but what it is that is deemed to be the result for the purpose of this distinction is a detail into which we need not enter (CP 5.45, 1903). Peirce also argues that […] the main distinction between the Inner and the Outer Worlds is that inner objects promptly take any modifications we wish, while outer objects are hard facts that no man can make to be other than they are. Yet tremendous as this distinction is, it is after all only relative. Inner objects do offer a certain degree of resistance and outer objects are susceptible of being modified in some measure by sufficient exertion intelligently directed (CP 5.45, 1903). Every sane person lives in a double world, the outer and the inner world, the world of percepts and the world of fantasy. And Peirce asks: “how exactly does the experience work?” It takes place by a series of surprises. There is no need of going into details. At one time a ship is sailing along in the trades over a smooth sea, the navigator having no more positive expectation than that of the usual monotony of such a voyage, when suddenly she strikes upon a rock. The majority of discoveries, however, have been the result of experimentation. Now no man makes an experiment without being more or less inclined to think that an interesting result will ensue; for experiments are much too costly of physical and psychical energy to be undertaken at random and aimlessly. And naturally nothing can possibly be learned from an experiment that turns out just as was anticipated. It is by surprises that experience teaches all she deigns to teach us (CP 5.51, 1903). 37 The experience is connected with and assimilated to the knowledge we already have, and receives an interpretation, or theory. Interpretation is linked to experience and experience is learning. Peirce wanted to show that the experience of duality of action and reaction is direct, but independent of our decision, and cannot be critically inferred from our previous cognitions, and to show it, Peirce had to prove that perceptual experience is not under our control. Through the perceptual experience of duality between our expectations and the objects, we get to know the indirect relationship between men and external objects. The phenomenon of surprise in itself is highly instructive in reference to this category because of the emphasis it puts upon a mode of consciousness which can be detected in all perception, namely, a double consciousness at once of an ego and a nonego, directly acting upon each other. Understand me well. My appeal is to observation — observation that each of you must make for himself (CP 5.52, 1903). Thus, existence as an element of Secondness is the mode of being of what is external and independent of thought. The reaction experienced by consciousness, which is a direct reaction, proves that there is an external reality. The experience of Secondness is immediate and specific, but in case it appears as a field of uniform response, it can be understood as a sign. Including the generality of Thirdness, the notion of reality is complete, because it is a way of thinking about individuals. In the dialogic view of representation, Peirce stated his realistic position when argued that if knowledge is general, it is due to the fact that reality, as we know it, is also general. At this point, attention will be drawn to the theory of perception. For Peirce, there is no thought without perception. At some point, every thought comes from perception and is constantly transformed by it. The thought-sign theory implies continuity, semiosis, Thirdness, because every thought or cognitive representation is a sign. Every reasoning and every thought is expressed by signs, and the Peircean sign is a complex triad relationship involving the sign, the object, and the interpreter. 38 In a way, the sign needs to be noticed before working as a sign and being merged with a pre-existing idea, concept or tendency to action, whoever the interpreter is. According to Peirce, only perception can change our habits. We just think through the signs and the signs are received by perception. Thus, taking into account that the sign is something that represents something else to somebody, an interpreter is necessary because otherwise the sign would not create another sign. For Peirce, there are three elements of perception: percept, percipuum and perceptual judgment. Peirce´s theory of perception is a triad theory and therefore it constitutes an attempt to break the dichotomy of the perceiving subject and the object that is perceived. Even though perception follows a triadic logic, it is under the control of Secondness, given the relationship between perception and action. When it comes to perception, the subject is passive; however, when it comes to action, it is active. When we perceive something we are aware of a duality in which there is something that turns against us, because the act of perceiving is external to the perceiver. Rosenthal (2001) summarizes the relationship among percept, percipuum and perceptual judgment as it follows: the present percept, interpreted in light of the ponecipuum, is the percipuum in its narrow sense. This percipuum is the result of the perceptual judgment in its narrow sense and ensures the “repeatable content", which serves to activate the habit, though, as an analytical stopping point, it provides no anticipation of future experience. The perceptual judgment in its narrow sense is the primitive abductive hypothesis of a present repetition of past experiential content, and the content in fact becomes a repetition of previously experienced contents only as the perceptual judgment assimilates it to those contents in the abductive process of recognition. Or, the percipuum is a recognition of the character of what is past. Haack (1994: 10) argues that Peirce´s theory is a very successful attempt “to escape from the limits of false dichotomy and understand the midfield’. Thus, the dichotomy between typical realism and inferentialism is overcome by Peirce's distinction between the perceptual judgment, the belief 39 that accompanies a perceptual experience, and the percept, the phenomenal, interactive aspect of a perceptual experience. Perception is a process through which we experience the action of the percept that is what presents itself to the subject´s perception. According to Peirce, only perception can change our habits. In 1885, Peirce claimed: The capital error of Hegel which permeates his whole system in every part of it is that he almost altogether ignores the Outward Clash.†9 Besides the lower consciousness of feeling and the higher consciousness of nutrition, this direct consciousness of hitting and of getting hit enters into all cognition and serves to make it mean something real. It is formal logic which teaches us this; not that of a Whateley or a Jevons, but formal logic in its new development, drawing nutriment from physiology and from history without leaving the solid ground of logical forms (CP 8.41, 1885). For Peirce, knowledge begins with perception, that is, the work of the mind in the face of the outer world, and the external shock as a form of Secondness would be our way of accessing reality; thus, real, which is the object of our research, can only be found through perception (HOOKWAY, 1985: 151). Knowledge takes its rise from the percept, which is the object perceived in a single act of perceiving. Is is impossível to report from self-observation what it is that takes place in the act of perception […] so rapid a succession of throes of perception, that the effect upon my distinct consciousness (which is limited to so much of my feeling as I can almost control) is that of a continuous flow (HP: 809). Knowledge, however, is not limited to perception, because it focuses on the future, it aims to anticipate the characteristics of future experience and the cognitive process that follows aims at establishing a rule or habit. But the continuity of thought is interrupted by the percept. With experience, the percept assaults our senses breaking the habitual state. 40 Suddenly, at an instant characterized by a sotong sense of newness, in which I seem to detect something corresponding to an indivisibility and an isolation of this now, (though this may be illusory), I experience a constraining force (implying a sense of resistance thereto) and a change of my habits of feeling brought instantly about with a present image of extraordinary detail and positiveness. (HP: 810) Percepts are not knowledge, but its starting point in a process in which many percepts and possible percepts are elaborated in propositions. From the observation, the effect of the outer world predominates, action and reaction. When action is suspended, an "imaginative habit" remains, but although the percept is a singular event, here and now, the memory seems to embody the characteristics of percepts. But the knowledge we are obliged to admit is that knowledge that is directly forced upon us. The percept consists of a unique event. But according to Peirce, even considering the perceptual facts, or immediate judgments we make concerning our unique percepts, the percept is the reality, but it is not in a propositional way. The most immediately judgment concerning it is abstract, which, however, is different from reality, although it must be accepted as true for this reality. Its truth is the fact that it is impossible to fix it, and the fact that it only claims to consider an aspect of the percept (CP 5568.1901). A percept contains only two types of elements: the ones belonging to both Firstness and Secondness (CP 7630, 1903). The immediate object of all knowledge and all thought is, ultimately, the percept, that knocks on the door of perception, blind, raw, insistent. The percept is a unique event that happens here and now. The percept may not be generalized without losing its essential character. It is a real battle between the ego and non-ego (CP 2.246, 1903). It is very insistent, for all its silence. It is a forceful thing. Yet it offers no reason, defence, nor excuse for its presence. It does not pretend to any right to be there. It silently forces itself upon me. 41 Such is the percept. Now what is its logical bearing upon knowledge and belief. This may be summed up in three items, as follows: 1st, it contributes something positive. (Thus, the chair has its four legs, seat, and back, its yellow color, its green cushion, etc. To learn this is a contribution to knowledge.) 2nd, it compels the perceiver to acknowledge it. 3rd, it neither offers any reason for such acknowledgment nor makes any pretension to reasonableness. This last point distinguishes the percept from an axiom. […] The percept, on the contrary, is absolutely dumb. It acts upon us, it forces itself upon us; but it does not address the reason, nor appeal to anything for support (CP 7.620-622, 1903) Therefore, percepts are raw, compulsive experiences made up of feelings, but Peirce expects to connect the character of irrational brute force of Secondness to the double consciousness involved in perception, in the perceptual experience as other than the subject. The percept is presented to the senses. Through perception we acquire information about the environment around us and the judgments we make are the result of a sensory contact with these objects, so a theory of perception must explain this connection: the sensory confrontation and the conceptual interpretation of what is perceived. It can be said that the process of knowledge begins with the percept breaking habits of feeling and giving way to images that, combined, can refer to a possible experience, involving the same event that gave rise to those percepts. The way the mind grasps the phenomenon is related to the theory of perception. In triadic logic of perception, the first is the sensory-motor apparatus. The percipuum, which is how the percept is translated by the sensory apparatus, is equivalent to the immediate object, without which the percept would not be noticed. The survival of human beings depends on this sensory-motor apparatus and the percipuum is how the sensory-motor apparatus will translate the percept. The judgment of perception is instantaneous because 42 the percipuum is immediately absorbed in our brain schemes, a continuum that Peirce names perceptual judgment. The percipuum is a recognition of the character of what is past, the percept which we think we remember. The interpretation is forced upon us; but no reason for it can be given. But just so when we experience a long series of systematically connected phenomena, suddenly the idea of the mode of connection, of the system, springs up in our minds, is forced upon us, and there is no warrant for it and no apparent explanation of how we were led so to view it. You may say that we put this and that together; but what brought those ideas out of the depths of consciousness? On this idea, which springs out upon experience of part of the system we immediately build expectations of what is to come and assume the attitude of watching for them. It is in this way that science is built up; and science would be impossible if man did not possess a tendency to conjecture rightly (CP 7.677-79, 1903). Percept is the second, because it plays the role of a dynamic object, and the perceptual judgement would be the third, equivalent to a proposition (interpreter). Perceptual judgments contain general elements, so that universal propositions are deducible from them in the manner in which the logic of relations shows that particular propositions usually, not to say invariably, allow universal propositions to be necessarily inferred from them (CP 5.541, 1902). What kind of judgment is the perceptual judgment? Peirce compares perceptual judgment to abductive inferences, that is, a reasoning method by which new hypotheses are suggested. Perceptual judgments are imposed to and accepted by us through a process we are unable to control and therefore criticize (CP 5.157, 1903). For Peirce, perceptual judgments are 43 the result of a process not sufficiently conscious to be controlled, or rather, not controllable and therefore not fully conscious. Both perceptual judgment and abduction are equally fallible, although the perceptual judgment cannot be doubted. There is something persistent and compulsive about perceptual judgment that makes us recognize it; on the other hand, abduction appears at those relaxing and playful moments when we do not know anything for sure. Peirce even says “but I will venture so far as to assert that every general form of putting concepts together is, in its elements, given in perception” (CP 5.186, 1903), because perceptual judgment is automated, usual perception that allows us to survive, “despite its apparent primitive features, every percept is the product of mental processes” (CP 7.624, 1903). But perceptual judgement is completely different from the percept: The percept is not the only thing that we ordinarily say we "perceive"; and when I professed to believe only what I perceived, of course I did not mean percepts, since percepts are not subjects of belief or disbelief. I meant perceptual judgments. Given a percept, this percept does not describe itself; for description involves analysis, while the percept is whole and undivided. But once having a percept, I may contemplate it, and say to myself, 'That appears to be a yellow chair'; and our usual language is that we "perceive" it to be a yellow chair, although this is not a percept, but a judgment about a present percept (CP 7.626, 1903). Or, I promised to show that a perceptual judgment is entirely unlike a percept. If it be true, as my analysis makes it to be, that a percept contains only two kinds of elements, those of firstness and those of secondness, then the great overshadowing point of difference is that the perceptual judgment professes to represent something, and thereby does represent something, whether truly or falsely. This is a very important difference, since the idea of representation 44 is essentially what may be termed an element of "Thirdness," that is, involves the idea of determining one thing to refer to another. The element of secondness in the percept consists in one part being relative to another. But the percept presents itself ready made, and contains no idea of any state of things being brought about. There is a rigid mathematical demonstration (which I cannot give here) that the idea of Firstness, or that of a positive suchness, and the idea of Secondness, or that of one thing's referring to another, can in no way be combined so as to produce the idea of one thing A, referring to a second, B, in the very act of referring to a third, C. This is the element of Thirdness, or mediation, which the conception of the representation of something to somebody obviously involves. In a perceptual judgment the mind professes to tell the mind's future self what the character of the present percept is. The percept, on the contrary, stands on its own legs and makes no professions of any kind (CP 7.630ff, 1903). Peirce´s theory of perception shows its realistic trend, giving priority to existing things over thought. Therefore, there are two types of effects: one of Firstness, when the percept reaches us in moments of perceptual availability and the mind is not full, and another of Secondness, of surprise or shock, when the mind is filled with expectation. “No cognition and no Sign is absolutely precise, not even a Percept” (CP 4.543, 1905), because every sign has a certain indetermination regarding the represented object, maintains a certain vagueness concerning the evolution of thought, yet it represents essential qualities of the object. Perception may fail, but can also be corrected if there are multiple types of access to the object, and what we perceive is the percept, which, according to Santaella (1993: 90), would be the greatest proof that Peirce presented in favor of realism. Based on his theory of perception, Peirce can solve some problems related to real as the perceptual source of our knowledge, the structure of 45 perception is linked to the origin of truth in Peirce´s theory. Understanding the theory of the object in Peirce's philosophy is crucial to the ontological and epistemological discussions of sign universe. For Peirce, the object determines the unity of the sign and the realistic philosophy provides justifications for the belief in the existence of a real world that is independent of what we may think or fantasize about it. Peirce suggests that by confrontation with the external objects the cognitive signs gain truth or falsity. So, then, a sign, in order to fulfill its office, to actualize its potency, must be compelled by its object. This is evidently the reason of the dichotomy of the true and the false. For it takes two to make a quarrel, and a compulsion involves as large a dose of quarrel as is requisite to make it quite impossible that there should be compulsion without resistance (CP 5.554, 1905). Peirce clearly distinguishes the thing in itself unknowable from the idea of knowable external reality independent of the representative function of the mind, which separates him from some pragmatists or coherentists such as Davidson (1986: 312) for whom there is no way of knowing what is causing the internal events of which we are aware: On the other hand, the instinctive truth of perceptual judgment is due to the correlation or coherence of the dynamic interpreter with the perceptual and emotional interpreter, and this coherent structure is both transparent and embedded in the perceptual judgment. This process is beyond our reasonable control, which we cannot decide if the result is true or false. Peirce suggests some tests that could be performed: The percepts, could I make sure what they were, constitute experience proper, that which I am forced to accept. But whether they are experience of the real world, or only experience of a dream, is a question which I have no means of answering with absolute certainty. I have, however, three tests which, though none of them is infallible, answer very well in ordinary cases (CP 2.142, 1902) 46 The first test consists in trying to dismiss the percepts: The first test consists in trying to dismiss the percepts. A fancy, or day-dream, can commonly be dismissed by a direct effort of will. If I find that the flow of percepts persists consistently in spite of my will, I am usually satisfied (CP 2.142, 1902). Still, it may be a hallucination, if there is reason to suspect that it is so, the second test can be applied. [the second test] consists in asking some other person whether he sees or hears the same thing. If he does, and if several people do, that will ordinarily be taken as conclusive. Yet it is an established fact that some hallucinations and illusions affect whole companies of people (CP 2.142, 1902) There remains a third test that can be applied, it is the safest of them: Namely, I may make use of my knowledge of the laws of nature (very fallible knowledge, confessedly) to predict that if my percept has its cause in the real world, a certain experiment must have a certain result—a result which in the absence of that cause would be not a little surprising. I apply this test of experiment. If the result does not occur my percept is illusory; if it does, it receives strong confirmation (CP 2.142, 1902). We can test and thus confirm or refute the perceptual judgment itself, not in the same process in which it is developed, but through a more controlled elaboration of the observation of the same object. Therefore, through the development of our knowledge and scientific research, we can distinguish the false from the true (CP 2141.1902), we can specially distinguish illusions or confirmed representations (CP 2.142, 1902). Although these tests may confirm the insistence on the real world, its existence is not provided by the immediate experience, but by our inferences derived from perceptual facts: 47 All these tests, however, depend upon inference. The data from which inference sets out and upon which all reasoning depends are the perceptual facts, which are the intellect's fallible record of the percepts, or "evidence of the senses." It is these percepts alone upon which we can absolutely rely, and that not as representative of any underlying reality other than themselves (CP 2.14, 1902). Since the 1860s, Peirce has always supported the theory that knowledge is derived from the outer world. Even the conclusions about our emotional and affective state are consequences of inferences from the outer world. But the impossibility of controlling and criticizing this almost inferential instinctual process (which is incorrigible) is not an absolute foundation of our knowledge. How then, in the cognitive process, is it possible to control it? In Peirce´s view, certainly not before the percept is formed. The machinery of the mind can only transform knowledge, but never originate it, unless it be fed with facts of observation (CP 5.392, 1903). This analysis can explain Peirce´s position against foundationalists, who accept the "given" as the foundation of knowledge. According to Rosenthal (2001), what is provided is not the absolute certainty of fundamentalist claims, but pragmatic certainty. The perception of an appearance is beyond conceivable doubt, because doubt it in the sense that it can actually be proved wrong is, literally, nonsense. In this discussion, Peirce highlights the crucial problems of the theory of knowledge and the knowledge of the external world that concern philosophy today. The naturalist idea of the evolution of knowledge and the method of discovering the truth through the trio of logical operations, the fallibility of human knowledge, hold for any knowledge, for everyday experience and for science or for philosophy. This is the rational method to make our ideas clear. The evidence of our negative knowledge of something external can be achieved by the analysis of Peirce´s epistemology. In 1904, the author 48 stated that “the highest grade of reality is only reached by signs” (CP 8.327, 1904). It worth emphasizing Peirce´s conception of reasoning: Reasoning, therefore, begins with premisses which are adopted as representing percepts, or generalizations of such percepts. All the reasoner's conclusions ought to refer solely to the percepts, or rather to propositions expressing facts of perception (CP 2.773, 1901). Peirce´s realism1 implies not only the consideration of a real object, independent of the outer world, but the recognition of the reality of universals. To nominalism, the continuum is only a matter of language. For nominalists, universals are just signs created to describe the quality of particular things. Nominalists refuse an objective correspondence of our concepts with the laws of nature, so the issue of nominalism and realism implies whether the truth of the laws or our logical inferences are objective or subjective, “the nominalists conceived the general element of cognition to be merely a convenience for understanding this and that fact. However, the realists looked upon the general, not only as the end and aim of knowledge, but also as the most important element of being” (CP 4.1, 1898). One of the prime doctrines of these men, for instance, a doctrine inherited from the pre-scientific ages, is that all generalization is a mere matter of convenience. The scientific man, on the other hand, without theorizing about generals, implicitly holds that laws are really operative in nature, and that the classification he is so painfully trying to find out is expressive of real facts. (N-58, 1894) 1 Peirce´s journey from Nominalism to Realism is discussed by Fisch (1986: 184-199) in five steps: “nominalist” (1867-1868), first step towards realism (1868), second step towards realism (1871), Pre-Monist period (1871-1890), and Monist period (1891-1914). See Bacha (1998). 49 Nature is in accordance with general laws, which actually determine how future events will occur, and these "formulas" are closely related to the characteristics of human reason, or […] that every scientific explanation of a natural phenomenon is a hypothesis that there is something in nature to which the human reason is analogous; and that it really is so all the successes of science in its applications to human convenience are witnesses (CP 1.316, 1903). In addition to this, nature was created a long time ago, but the process of becoming more and more to human reason still continues. A law is under Thirdness, it is mediation, a law can be seen as generalization of a particular case because for a law to be true all the possible facts should obey this rule. Realism is not a hypothesis about the past, but about science as a "socio-historical" process that allows predictions about the future: […] to my notions there can be no mystery in the universe, in the sense of a real fact to which no approach to knowledge can ever be gained. For a reality is an idea that insists upon proclaiming itself, whether we like it or not. There may be a question that no amount of research can ever answer. If so, there is a lacuna in the completeness of reality. But these things usually called mysteries are simply cases in which questions cannot be answered for the reason that no definite meaning can be attached to them (CP 8.156, 1901). In the context of Peirce's philosophy, scientific research is an activity focused on an end that is the discovery of truth and in the realistic view, science progresses by convergence toward truth in the sense of correspondence with reality. This is an important element, because the very validity of induction is related to predictions, not as a basis for action, but as validity of the scientific method, as a way to uncover the truth. If a theory explains the facts 50 submitted to it, it can be considered true, and a theory is true because it predicts the course of future events very well. Peirce´s continuum theory intends to demonstrate that nature has continuity from the past to the future, which is the very legitimacy of the laws of nature and induction, because otherwise there would be no representation. It is the regularity, generality, continuity that allow the representation. But if, on the other hand, it be conceivable that the secret should be disclosed to human intelligence, it will be something that thought can compass. Now thought is of the nature of a sign. In that case, then, if we can find out the right method of thinking and can follow it out — the right method of transforming signs — then truth can be nothing more nor less than the last result to which the following out of this method would ultimately carry us. In that case, that to which the representation should conform, is itself something in the nature of a representation, or sign — something noumenal, intelligible, conceivable, and utterly unlike a thing-in-itself (CP 5.553, 1905). 51 PART II WOULD THE TRUTH BE THE BEST GOAL FOR SCIENTIFIC INQUIRY? The man of science has received a deep impression of the majesty of truth, as that to which, sooner or later, every knee must bow. He has further found that his own mind is sufficiently akin to that truth, to enable him, on condition of submissive observation, to interpret it in some measure. As he gradually becomes better and better acquainted with the character of cosmical truth, and learns that human reason is its issue and can be brought step by step into accord with it, he conceives a passion for its fuller revelation. He is keenly aware of his own ignorance, and knows that personally he can make but small steps in discovery (CP 8.136). But the question is, whether, granting that there be such a thing as truth , which can be ascertained at all, such a way of adding conclusion to premiss, as that under examination, would lead to the ascertainment of the truth by the speediest path, or not. The whole logical inquiry relates to the truth; now the very idea of truth is that it is quite independent of what you or I may think it to be. How we think, therefore, is utterly irrelevant to logical inquiry (CP 2.55). 52 1. CATEGORIZATION OF THEORIES OF TRUTH Truth is not the sort of thing one should expect to have a philosophically interesting theory about (Rorty, 1995). “What is truth”? we sometimes ask – but the question tends to be rethorical conveying the somewhat defeatist idea that a good answer, if indeed there is such a thing, will be subtle, so profound and so hard to find, that to look for one would surely be a waste of time (Horwich, 1999: 1). When a man desires ardently to know the truth, his first effort will be to imagine what that truth can be. He cannot prosecute his pursuit long without finding that imagination unbridled is sure to carry him off the track (CP 1.46, 1896). But if a man occupies himself with investigating the truth of some question for some ulterior purpose, such as to make money, or to amend his life, or to benefit his fellows, he may be ever so much better than a scientific man, if you will — to discuss that would be aside from the question — but he is not a scientific man (CP 1.45, 1896). This chapter presents a brief overview of many projects on theories of truth establishing the context of Peirce´s theory. According to Rorty (1967:35): In our culture, the notions of “science”, “racionality”, “objetivity”, and “truth” are bound up with one another. Science is thought of as offering a solid “hard” and “objetive” truth; truth as correspondence to reality, the only sort of truth worthy of the name (Rorty, 1967:35). Rorty (1967) and Searle (1993) point out that the relationship between reality and thought have a long history in the Western tradition, and involves a particular conception of truth, reason, reality, rationality, logic, knowledge, justification and demonstration, which are so important that 53 somehow would define this tradition. For Searle, the simplest definition of science would aim to formulate a set of true sentences in the form of theories, which are true because they approximately correspond to a reality independent of thought. Thus, for the concept of Western metaphysics underlying the concept of Western science, the foundational principle would be realism, according to which reality exists independently of human representations. Searle also argues that there are many theories of truth, but the correspondence theory of truth is the most important to the Western tradition. The idea of truth as something to be pursued for its own sake, not because it will be good for oneself, or one´s real or imaginary community, is the central theme of this tradition (Western) (Rorty, 1987:21). Goodman (2001) argues that the truth has been widely attacked and when philosophers meet to discuss ways of knowledge or belief, some treat the word truth as something shameful. Others consider dogmatic or fascist those who believe that there really is a truth to be known, and that this truth can be of any kind. Thus, it is not surprising that a review of literature brings a widely variety of divergent concepts and theories, especially when considering areas such as semantics, logic, epistemology or ontology. One of the most profound differences is about whether the notion of truth would be epistemic, ontological, linguistic, pragmatic, or whether the notion of truth would be substantial or deflationary. It is worth mentioning that this study does not intend to answer questions like: what are the philosophical issues of truth? or what questions should a theory of truth answer? In fact the truth predicate exists solely for the sake of a certain logical need (Horwich, 1998:2). The concept of truth has a dual, interesting and exciting nature, because on one hand it is a clear and simple idea, but on closer examination, the apparent clarity and simplicity may lead to logical contradictions and insoluble problems. 54 According to Chauí (1994: 98-99), our common concepts of truth depend greatly on meanings that emerge from linguistic differences. In Greek, truth is aletheia, with reference to what is not hidden or concealed. Aletheia is the opposite of pseudos, which is exactly what is hidden or concealed. When aletheia predominates, truth is in things themselves, or in reality itself, and the mark of true knowledge is the evidence. On the other hand, still according to Chauí (1994: 98-99), the Latin word for truth is veritas, and it refers to the accuracy of a description, or the level of accuracy of a story. Truth here is not about the quality of things, but how accurate, exact and detailed a narrative is. When veritas prevails, it is considered that truth depends on precision and accuracy in creating and using language rules. Besides, it is important to keep in mind that the Hebrew word for truth (emunah) refers to what was agreed upon for the present or the future, and has to do with the expectation that something that was arranged or agreed will happen for sure. When emunah predominates, truth depends on a reliance agreement or a pact of trust among researchers. Gadamer (2002: 46) draws attention to the privileged relationship between truth and science. For him, it is clear that science "has created the Western civilization, especially its unique mode of being and uniqueness," and aletheia properly means "unblinding", that is, truth is "unblinding". Carrilho (1990, p.31) explains that the problem of truth is presented according to two approaches, genealogical and epistemological, which correspond to two ways of thinking about the relationship knowledge / truth. In the first case, the emphasis is not only on justifying the knowledge, but also using the scientific knowledge as a model; and in the other, the importance and meaning of this same model is questioned. Blackburn & Simmons (1999: 1) argue that truth “characterizes only some of the things we might say or believe”. Truth is abstract in that it can apply to propositions of any kind, on any subject matter. But what do true propositions share, or what do the false ones lack? Suppose we call the things we might say or believe, propositions (there are some choices about that, but for the moment we ignore them) then truth is 55 similarly abstract in that it can apply to propositions of any kind, on any subject matter (Blackburn & Simmons, 1999:1). Musgrave (1999:247) claims that the philosophical problem of truth would be Pilate's question. It refers to two issues: 1. What is truth? That is, what does it mean to say of something that is true? And 2. What is true? That is, what is the truth about the matter in which we are interested (whatever it is). And how do we find out the truth of the matter? According to the author, the second question is more important than the first, but until we know what the word true means (the first), we cannot set investigating the second. Da Costa (1997: 22) explains that knowledge finds itself correlated with truth. Both knowledge and logic "find themselves intertwined with each other," because they depend on the truth. Also, from the epistemological point of view, truth and justification are two concepts that are connected. As for Kirkham (1997: 49), the justification must be defended or discussed with reference to the truth, or as it is usually said, the concept of justification presupposes the truth. However, there are authors who disagree with this point of view, such as Rorty (1979: 280), for whom theories about truth and meaning are unnecessary. According to him, the thesis of justification / truth is often defended only as input to other doctrines and would just be a way to express the hypothesis that there is really no philosophical program in which the truth can play its role. Thus, we would not need any theory of truth distinct from the theory of justification. Also for Rorty, the thesis of justification would be a metaphor for the thesis that the truth is related to a conceptual scheme or a way of denying that the truth has any epistemological value. Some authors (such as Strawson, 1950 or Putnan, 1971) argue that it is inappropriate or even nonsense to say that the statements are true. Thus, to admit what sentences are, one can explore the grammatical structure in the definition of truth, as in some versions of the correspondence theory, especially Tarski's semantic theory. Although the sentences clearly have grammatical structure, utterances and propositions do not, because they are 56 extralinguistic. Thus, the plausibility of Tarski's theory could be a reason to consider sentences as the bearers of truth. Even though there are several categories of theories of truth, Kirkham´s theory (1995: 20) seems to be the most complete and appropriate for the scope of this study, as shown in the table below, although in the course of this chapter we mention other categories such as Blackburn & Simmons (1999) and Musgrave (1999). Kirkham (1995: 20) proposes three main categories for theories of truth: the metaphysical project, the justification project and the speech-act project. The metaphysical project would aim to identify what the truth is, or, what a true proposition would be. This project has three branches, which are the extensional, naturalistic and essence. Also according to Kirkham, the answers to the level of the metaphysical project can be divided into two broad categories: realistic and unrealistic theories. Realist theories include those historically named theories of correspondence and the unrealistic ones include semantics, coherence and redundancy. Regarding the justification project, some philosophers have sought to discover what kind of evidence can be used to determine whether a given proposition is likely to be true or not. What counts as relevant evidence varies according to each kind of proposition, whether it is related to physical or abstract objects. Theories of justification answer questions such as: for a given proposition (belief or statement), when and how it is possible to justify that it is true. As for the speech-act project, it aims to describe locutionary and illocutionary purposes that use expressions that seem to ascribe the quality of truth to any proposition. They can be classified into illocutionary, assertion or attribution. Table 2 summarizes this categorization. 57 Table 2 - Categorization of theories of truth 1. The metaphysical Project A. The extensional project Philosopher Alfred Tarski Saul Kripke B. The naturalistic Project C. The essence project Philosopher C.S.Peirce William James Bertrand Russel J. L. Austin Brand Blanshard Paul Horwich 2. The justification Project Philosopher F.H.Bradley William James Brand Blanshard (many others) 3. The speech-act Project A. The ilocutionary act project Philosopher P.F.Strawson Huw Price B. The assertion Project The assertion project The ordinary (naive?) person The deep structure Project Philosopher F.P. Ramsey Alan White C.J.F. Williams Grover, Camp and Belnap Theoretical school Semantic theory Semantic theory Theoretical school Pragmaticism Instrumentalism Correspondence theory Correspondence theory Coherence theory Minimal theory Theoretical school Coherence theory Instrumentalism Coherence theory Foundationalism Theoretical school Performantive theory Darwinian theory Theoretical school Redundance theory Appraisal theory Redundancy theory “Prossentential” theory Fonte: Kirkham (1995:37).2 2 According to Kirkham (1999), Field, Davidson and Dummet have been excluded from this list for not having a theory of truth, and supporting other kinds of projects. 58 Musgrave (1999: 149) classifies the truth in objective and subjective; so if one defines truth not as the relationship between beliefs and the external world but as “some internal quality of beliefs” and assuming that the “believer” may know if this belief is true, then the “believer” may also know the truth what Musgrave calls subjective truth. According to this classification and regarding the first type, the general formulations are: • • • To say of what is that it is not, or of what is not that it is, is false, while to say of what is that it is, and of what is not that it is not, is true; A statement is true if and only if what it states to be the case really is the case; A statement is true if and only it corresponds to the facts. And regarding the second type, the subjective theories, the general formulations are: • • • • • • • The self-evidence theory: a belief is true if and only if it is self-evident to me; The indubitability theory: a belief is true if and only if I cannot doubt it; The clear and distinct perception theory: a belief is true if and only if I perceive (conceive) it clearly and distinctly; The coherence theory: a belief is true if and only if it coheres with the rest of my beliefs; The pragmatist theory: a belief is true if and only if I find useful to have it; The verifiability theory: a belief is true if and only if it is confirmed by my experience; The consensus theory: a belief is true if and only if my intellectual community agrees that it is. But according to Musgrave (1999), an objection made to subjective theories is that they can lead to relativism, that is, a proposition can be true or coherent, or confirmed by experience to an individual and not to another. 59 Subjetivism about truth entails relativism, and that flies in the face of two laws of truth, the law of excluded middle and the law of contradition (Musgrave, 1999:254). Blackburn & Simmons (1999: 1-29) classify the theories of truth into two types: traditional theories of truth and minimalist theories. Traditional theories of truth are basically four: the correspondence theory, the coherence theory, the pragmatist theory and the theory of optimal verification. The minimalist theories belong to the semantic field, and the main theories are the deflationary theory, Ramsey´s redundancy theory, and Davidson´s semantic theory. Picture 1 Theories of Truth Source: Haack (2006:87) 60 2. PEIRCE AND THE THEORY OF TRUTH: correspondence or convergence? Peirce, however conceived of himself as an architectonic philosopher and so in order to get a grip on what he thought about truth, one must make serious excursions into pragmatism, theory of signs, fallibilism, critical commonsensism, logic, categories and scholastic realism (Myzak, 1991: Preface) Correspondence theory: a statement is true if and only if it corresponds with facts. Coherence theory: a statement is true if and only if coheres with some specific set of other statements we hold (Blackburn & Simon, 1999: 781) The correspondence theory of truth comes from Aristotle's definition, that is, for a proposition to be true it must correspond to the facts. This Aristotelian explanation introduces a distinction between being as something real and being itself comprising a multiplicity of ways of being. So "X is true if X corresponds to a fact." Blackburn & Simon (1999) claim that the correspondence theory of truth "is a commonplace that no one denies". But the difficulties begin when we try to dissect the notions involved. The definition of truth, according to the theory of correspondence, leads to a discussion about what a fact is. What kind of thing is a fact? What kind of correspondence is in question? And for that matter what kind of thing is a proposition? For some authors, the definition of fact (as something that actually happens, or as something that is true, or how something corresponds to the truth) falls into a vicious circle. Some have taken propositions to be creatures of the mind [...] others take propositions to be abstract structures…[…] still others hope to dispense with propositions in favour of sentences…(Blackburn & Simon, 1999 2). 61 According to Haack (2006: 26), both Russell and Wittgenstein, during the period of "logical atomism", defined truth as the correspondence of a proposition with a fact, for they aspired to device a unique, ideally language in which logical form would be perfectly exhibited. Blackburn & Simon (1999: 2) argue that some philosophers are pessimistic about our ability to answer these questions, they think the answers traditionally given generate insuperable problems. There would be two alternatives. On one hand, the authors try to find something more than just correspondence with facts to find out what the truth is; this is the direction taken by Bradley, Joachim, giving rise to the coherentist theory of truth, or James and the utility, giving rise to the pragmatist theory of truth . Some think that people trying to describe a correspondence relation make a category mistake, by turning facts into complexes of things, which they are not .[…] Some think that the theory requires a separation between the mind, as the domain of facts (Blackburn& Simon, 1999:2). Bradley (1999:36) claims that “the end of truth is to be and to possess reality in an ideal form”. For Joachim (1999: 46-52): Truth, we said, was the systematic coherence which characterized a significant whole. And as we proceed to identify a significant whole with “an organized individual experience, self-fulfilling and sel-fulfilled” […] Hence the truth, which our sketch describe, is – from the point of view of human intelligence – an Ideal and an Ideal which can never as such, or in its completeness, be actual as human experience (Joachim, 1999:46-52). James (1907) says that “truth, as any dictionary will tell you, is a property of certain o four ideas. It means agreement, as falsity means disagreement, with reality.” In the second alternative, the authors deny that there actually is a real project to discover what the truth is; this is the position of those who oppose the correspondence theory of truth (Blackburn & Simon, 1999). In 62 this context, Haack (2006: 95) notices a persistent difficulty with the correspondence theory has been “the difficulty of supplying a precise amount of ‘corresponds’” although a similar problem occurs with the coherence theory because it “needs to be specified exactly what the appropriate relations between beliefs must be them to be coherent in the required sense”. Davidson (1990) criticizes realism and the correspondence theory of truth. For him, the truth would not be the aim of the investigation. The correspondence theory of truth would aim to find substantial evidence for our beliefs, and there is nothing more we can do than trying to stabilize our convictions. The truth is not a norm that can be added to norm (norms) of justifications. Thus: Even if we are persuaded that the concept of truth cannot be defined, the intuition or hope remains tat we can characterize truth using some fairly simple formula (Davidson, 1999: 310). Davidson (1999) claims that “truth as correspondence with reality may be an idea we are better off without...”, especially when the words truth and reality are capitalized. For Davidson, "the formulation is not as wrong as empty, but it has the merit of suggesting that something should not be true just because it is believed, even if each and every person believes in it”. The problem of truth by correspondence rests on the assertion that the formula has an explanatory power; however, there would be good reasons to skepticism regarding the importance of the theory of truth by correspondence: Truth is, as G.E.Moore, Bertrrand Russel, and Gottlob Frege mantained, and Alfred Tarski proved, an indefinable concept. This does not mean we can say notinhing revealing about it: we can, by realting it to other concepts like belief, desire, cause and action. Nor does the indefinability of truth imply that the concept is mysterious, ambigouous, or untrustworthy (Davidson, 1999: 309). 63 According to Putnam (1997: 169), for both Peirce and James, the opinion of those who investigate is ultimately the one they “tend to consider” to be the truth. This would be the constitutive explanation for the truth. Da Costa (1997: 114), however, argues that in physics there are concepts such as probability wave, quarks or phase space, which make it difficult to accept that they actually correspond to traces of real, resembling more the categories created by man. The empirical sciences use theories or laws that "are known not to reproduce reality", for example, Maxwell's electromagnetic theory or Lavoisier´s law, "although they are not strictly true." In this context, Souza (2000) believes that today it is accepted that the various theories formulated by the scientist, in the fields of both natural and human sciences, are destined to be in the near or distant future overcome by the discovery of phenomena that distort them. Therefore, no researcher can simply accept that his theories are true (in the sense of the theory by correspondence). For Haack (2006: 88), it is common to make a distinction between definitions of truth and criteria of truth, and it is necessary to carefully deal with this issue. However, one cannot simply refrain from using this distinction, even if it is "problematic", because of its importance to the rivalry between the theory of correspondence3 and the theory of coherence: [...]the idea is, roughly, that whereas a definition gives the meaning the word “true”, a criterion gives a test by means of o tell whether a sentence (or whatever) is true or false [...] (Haack, 2006: 88) The categorization of theory of truth is a controversial issue among scholars of Peirce. For some, Peirce chose a correspondence theory of truth and thereby true propositions are simply the result of the final opinion of the 3 Coherence theories take truth to consist in relations of coherence among a set of beliefs. Correspondence theories take the truth of a proposition to consist, not in its relations to other propositions, but in relation to the world, its correspondence to the facts. Peirce, James and Dewey offer characteristically pragmatic accounts of truth which combine coherence and correspondence elements (Haack, 2006: 86). 64 scientific community (Thompson, 1952, Scheffer 1994, Rescher, 2000, and Haack, 1978). Do you think, reader, that it is a positive fact that "Truth, crushed to earth, shall rise again," or do you think that this, being poetry, is only a pretty fiction? Do you think that, notwithstanding the horrible wickedness of every mortal wight, the idea of right and wrong is nevertheless the greatest power on this earth, to which every knee must sooner or later bow or be broken down; or do you think that this is another notion at which common sense should smile? (CP 1.217 de 1902). All positive reasoning is of the nature of judging the proportion of something in a whole collection by the proportion found in a sample. Accordingly, there are three things to which we can never hope to attain by reasoning, namely, absolute certainty, absolute exactitude, absolute universality (CP 1.141 de 1897). For others, the correspondence theory of truth would be an ideal limit to scientific progress (Levi, 1980, Quine4, 1960). To them, science is a body of well-justified beliefs in the pursuit of truth, which will not be affected even if its progress continues forever. There is a third group that argues that for Peirce true propositions are a matter of correspondence between language and the world, so some true propositions correspond to what the scientific community endorses as a final conclusion in case the research continues (Thompson, 1953, Hilpinen, 1982). In this view, truth is not a regulative concept and will never be discovered unless asymptotically. Also, there are scholars who consider Peirce's theory of truth a theory of coherence. For them, there is no relationship between the opinion of the scientific community and the extra linguistic world. Altshuler (1982: 43) notes that, in 1867, in his review of Venn´s "The Logic of Chance", Peirce 4 Like Quine, Peirce insisted that there is no knowledge in philosophy other than empirical science and that logic is methodologically compatible with natural science, telling something about things are. 65 argues that "truth is the agreement of representation with its object" (CP 8.3, 1867). The fact that Peirce believes that truth consists in the existence of a fact corresponding to the true proposition (CP 2.652, 1877) and that truth is the correspondence of representation with its object (CP 5.553, 1905), scholars such as Rescher (1994, 2000, 2005) and Haack (1978) considered Peirce fundamentally committed to the correspondence theory of truth. However, when analyzing what is involved in the correspondence relation, what is observed is that he rarely talks about combining thought with an interpreted reality, showing that he might be more concerned with the correspondence of a given belief with the ultimate ideal. As much as James and Dewey, Peirce would consider truth as correspondence in terms of the relationship between cognitive entities (Altshuler, 1982: 43). According to Altshuler (1982), when Peirce talks about correspondence, he refers to the topics which we potentially have cognitive access to. Both James and Dewey argue that truth involves a relation of correspondence or agreement, but the nature of this relationship can only be determined by a pragmatic analysis. James’ position was first presented in 1884 in "The Function of Cognition", which presents a point of view that he later adopted to disseminate the power of Royce´s argument for an absolute mind as the only possible reference. Briefly, the relationship between an idea and its object is the function of that idea leading to some unexpected experiences. The fact that designed experiences are available in appropriate circumstances, in part constitutes the truth of the representation in question. The agreement involving the truth is the agreement between ideas. It is the correspondence between an expected experience and experience itself that actually happens in relevant circumstances, then the truth is not a relationship between our ideas and non-human realities, but between conceptual parts of our experience and sensational parts. Dewey also specifies the corresponding relation of truth and a connection between cognitive entities. 66 The relation gets the fulfillment of a purpose, a plan and its execution, and the result is the verification or the success of the initial belief that certain actions would lead to certain consequences. It can be seen that Peirce uses the notion of correspondence in the same way as James and Dewey, and the truth would not be defended in terms of the relationship between the representation and the thing itself. To support these considerations, Altshuler refers to CP 5.5535, 1905, in which Peirce argues that the nature of the correspondence is not specified in human terms, then the truth would have no meaning for us. In order to avoid this, truth is defined as the final result to which we would be taken when following the method of science. In this case, the representation would conform to something that is the nature of the representation or sign – “something nomological, conceivable, and definitely a thing-in-itself". Hookway (2000: 78) relates the truth in Peirce with convergence, correspondence and reference. From the point of view of truth by convergence, the analysis is related to the idea of science as a sociohistorical research process (CP 7:54, 1902), emphasizing science as a way of life. Regarding the view of truth by correspondence, Hookway highlights the passage "truth is that concordance of an abstract statement with the ideal limit towards which endless investigation would tend to bring scientific belief, which concordance the abstract statement may possess by virtue of the confession of its inaccuracy and one-sidedness" (CP 5.565, 1901). This conception shows that true propositions provide iconic representations of reality. From the point of view of truth by reference, it is important to emphasize the role of ratings in Peirce's theory, as well as the concepts related to the theory of perception and the theory of knowledge (CP 5.384, 1877) 6. 5 6 This passage was mentioned on pages 47 and 81 This passage was presented on page 27. 67 According to Rorty (1999: 328), Peirce in his earlier period wanted to avoid both the revisionary metaphysics of idealism and the promissory notes of physicalism. He shared with the idealist and the physicalist the motive of refuting the sceptic, but he thought it enough to say that “reality” means somthibng like “whatever we sall still be asserting the existence of at the end of inquity”. This definition of reality briedges the gap the s etic sees between coherence and correspondence (Rorty, 1999: 328). On the other hand, in CP 7.187, 1901, Peirce is clear about the nature of correspondence when he claimed that the scientific truth is “the agreement with that ultimate proposition that we look forward to, — agreement with that, whatever it may turn out to be”. And also: No modification of the point of view taken, no selection of other facts for study, no natural bent of mind even, can enable a man to escape the predestinate opinion (CP 5.407 de 1897) Or, […] it is the predestined ultimate idea, which is independent of what you, I, or any number of men may persist, for however long, in thinking, yet which remains thought, after all (CP 8.103 de 1900). The analysis of the passages mentioned suggests a theory of truth by correspondence, because they ensure that the true proposition is one that accurately describes a world whose properties are logically and causally independent of minds7. 7 See CP 5.406, 8.153, 3.129 or 6.495; CP 5.416, 1905 or 5.407, 1893 or 8.126, 1902, or 5.554, 1906 or 2.135, 1902 and 5.384, 1877. 68 But Peirce emphasizes that "beyond the realm of truth and falsity verification lose their meanings" (Nation, 57, 1893) or a hypothesis is true when certain predictions based on it have been verified by it (MS 473: 23). Peirce defines truth in terms of scientific inference to be achieved by the community, that is, as correspondence and coherence, because in the context of Peirce's philosophy, scientific research is an activity focused on one end, which is the discovery of truth. In the realist view, science progresses by convergence toward truth, in the sense of correspondence with reality. This is an important element, because the very validity of induction is related to predictions, not as a basis for action, but as validity of the scientific method, as a way to uncover the truth. Savan (1964) and Rescher (1978) argue that Peirce adopts a correspondence theory of truth along with a criterion of truth by coherence. One could say that, especially after the 1900s, Peirce's ideas about the truth are closely related to his strong defense of realism. According to Rescher's argument (2000: 11), the pragmatic view of truth in Peirce is understandably coordinated with effective implementation. But this must be understood considering the background of some assumptions, because a pragmatic theory of truth is always construed with reference to a criterion that assess the claims to truth of a factual contention in terms of the success engendered by its acceptance. But for Peirce this criterion is neither immediately nor simply the factor of its applicative success, but, “Truth is that concordance of an abstract statement with the ideal limit towards which endless investigation would tend to bring scientific belief…” (CP 5.565, 1901). On the other hand, there is an instinctive mechanism in human cognition that allows us to acquire rational knowledge of reality, probably like other animals that are also confronted with reality, but that only acquire more practical knowledge. This basic mechanism is called by Peirce the "natural instinct for truth"8 8 Also see CP 7.220, 1903 or CP 7.77, 1882 or CP 2.176, 1902 or CP 5.212, 1903 or CP 5.554, 1906. 69 In examining the reasonings of those physicists who gave to modern science the initial propulsion which has insured its healthful life ever since, we are struck with the great, though not absolutely decisive, weight they allowed to instinctive judgments. Galileo appeals to il lume naturale at the most critical stages of his reasoning. Kepler, Gilbert, and Harvey — not to speak of Copernicus — substantially rely upon an inward power, not sufficient to reach the truth by itself, but yet supplying an essential factor to the influences carrying their minds to the truth. (CP 1.80, 1896). Side by side, then, with the well established proposition that all knowledge is based on experience, and that science is only advanced by the experimental verifications of theories, we have to place this other equally important truth, that all human knowledge, up to the highest flights of science, is but the development of our inborn animal instincts (CP 2.754, 1883). For Almeder (1982: 64), Peirce has never distanced himself from his realistic commitment, and therefore the nature of truth by correspondence would be incompatible with his fallibilism. Regarding the contemporary authors, Dummett´s realism involves an assessment of meaning dependent on truth, but his verificationist theory of meaning is antirealist. Goodman in turn declares himself a radical relativist, and the truth would only be relevant to denotational systems. Quine (1999), though not explicitly antirealist, can also be placed in the perspective of others because of his rejection of metaphysical realism. For Quine, truth is related to a theory, in which it is stated the terms of discourse. Truth hinges on reality, but to object, on this score, to calling sentences true, is a confusion. Where the truth predicate has its utility is in just those places, where, though still concerned with reality, we are impelled by certain technical complications to mentions sentences (Quine, 1999: 144). 70 Peirce´s theory of truth was developed in accordance with his realist theory of knowledge, in which reality and truth are two closely related concepts. Peirce was always interested in the truth, because he believed it was the main goal of science, that is, one would reach the truth through the use of the scientific method. His first conception of truth was presented in 1868, in an attack on the Cartesian epistemology. By defining truth as an established opinion at the end of a scientific research, he sets a standard view that rejects causal realism as an explanation for knowledge. To the argument from universal and hypothetical propositions, the reply is, that though their truth cannot be cognized with absolute certainty, it may be probably known by induction (CP 5.258, 1868) In his criticism of nominalism (in which the role of reasoning is undermined, since it does not provide established truths about a world known by the effects of sensations, unless it is granted by God) comes an understanding of reality as well as an evolutionary concept of truth. As Peirce develops his view of reality in order to make it equivalent to the truth itself, and the final theory becomes its own object, reality becomes an ideal entity due to final causation (telos) of research progress. Peirce's ideas about the scientific method are particularly connected to his conception of truth, which in turn can be seen as a type of semiosis9. In fact, the specific kind of correspondence involved in Peirce´s theory of truth can be conceived as a kind of semiotic relationship. In CP 5.311, 1868, Peirce claimed that “those two series of cognition — the real and the unreal — consist of those which, at a time sufficiently future, the community will always continue to re-affirm; and of those which, under the same conditions, will ever after be denied”, which will be later resumed: 9 Generating or producing another sign is proper to sign action, a process that Peirce calls semiosis. 71 [...] the ideal limit towards which endless investigation would tend to bring scientific belief, which concordance the abstract statement may possess by virtue of the confession of its inaccuracy and one-sidedness, and this confession is an essential ingredient of truth (CP 5.565, 1901). In 1871, Peirce argues that “all human opinion universally tends in the long run to a definite form, which is the truth”. Let any human being have enough information and exert enough thought upon any question, and the result will be that he will arrive at a certain definite conclusion, which is the same that any other mind will reach under sufficiently favorable circumstances (CP 8.12, 1871). In 1873, Peirce claims that “truth is a character which attaches to an abstract proposition, such as a person might utter. It essentially depends upon that proposition´s not professing to be exactly true” (CP 5.565, 1901). In 1878, “truth consists in the existence of a real fact corresponding to the true proposition”. For Peirce, “the truth of the hypothetical proposition that if the premises be true the conclusion will also be true” (CP 2.652, 1878). On the other hand, the decision about the truth or falsity of any belief is only possible through knowledge, and this decision is not immediate. Investigating is to inquire and try to get answers, it is to increasingly reinforce a certain belief. But there is a question that can be asked based on the first version of the truth: will the reality be represented only at the end of the investigation, when the final opinion is reached? This issue will only be settled from the 1900s on, with the use of “would-be´s”. In “Truth and Reality: Putnan and the Pragmatic Conception of Truth”, Hookway (n.d.) summarizes the evolutionary path of the notion of truth in Peirce´s work. The author separates Peirce's views before and after 1880. In 1877-8, the convergence thesis is preponderant. Peirce’s earlier formulations of the convergence thesis form part of an explanation of the concept of reality. 72 Peirce’s formulations of the convergence thesis after 1880 qualify this confidence that we shall always eventually reach a fated convergence. The passage (CP 4.32) suggests a considerable weakening of the claims from 1877-8. Transforming the commitment to convergence into a hope, a regulative ideal, is a pervasive feature of his later writings. As Peirce’s philosophy developed after 1878, he soon came to give his account of truth a regulative status. After 1900, Peirce challenged the ‘virtual assumption that what is relative to thought cannot be real’ (CP 5.430, 1905). According to Hookway (n.d.), Peirce´s first definitions of truth would be part of the clarification of the concept of reality (reality as the object of true opinion). They would represent his eagerness to develop metaphysics from logic, for which he needed a logical analysis of truth in order to identify a set of true propositions with reference to its destination in the research process. In the 1877-8 period, an absolute conception of truth and reality could be found in Peirce´s writings, especially “How to make our ideas Clear” and “Fixation of Belief”. It would be a worldview independent of our experience, disregarding all that refers to a particular perspective and avoiding dependence on any feature of our cognitive apparatus, a conception mostly independent of our perspectives and peculiarities: The opinion which is fated to be ultimately agreed to by all who investigate is what we mean by the truth, and the object represented in this opinion is the real. That is the way I would explain reality (CP 5.407, 1877). After 1880, Peirce would have developed a new way to explain our thoughts about reality (external things would be directly perceived). The formulations after 1880 would show confidence that we would always reach this predestined convergence. But, by fate, one can also understand the consolidation of researchers´ opinion, a view that is bound to find the real and truth means something that the research shows. Around 1903, Peirce would introduce the immediate object of perception. In “What Pragmatism Is” (1905), Peirce resumes his initial ideas about truth and reality, explaining that the predestined opinion "controlled by a rational experimental logic" does not depend on any accidental 73 circumstance, “however the perversity of thought of whole generations may cause the postponement of the ultimate fixation” (CP 5.430, 1905). Hausman (1993) reinforces this idea by stating that a general cannot be thought of without a telos, with respect to being a habit, a third, the general is what it is due to its influence on its future instances, that is, what is truly real is necessarily connected to the general idea that it represents. Peirce´s theory of truth results from the application of the pragmatic principle to the clarification of concepts, a principle which is advocated as an appropriate methodological rule for these purposes, based on his theory of signs. Briefly, Peirce defines genuine sign as a relational process among three terms (sign, object, interpretant), and the sign action itself generates or produces another sign, a process called semiosis. In the triadic relation among sign, object and interpretant, everything has a semiotic nature. This is not a simple triadic relation, but a complex of triadic relations, which can be thought of in three different ways, depending on the emphasis that is placed on each of the correlates. If the sign is emphasized, it is a relationship of meaning or representation. If the object is put in evidence, it is a relationship of objectification. And finally, if the interpreter is emphasized, it is a relationship of interpretation. Genuine mediation is the character of a Sign. A Sign is anything which is related to a Second thing, its Object, in respect to a Quality, in such a way as to bring a Third thing, its Interpretant, into relation to the same Object, and that in such a way as to bring a Fourth into relation to that Object in the same form, ad infinitum. If the series is broken off, the Sign, in so far, falls short of the perfect significant character (CP 2.92, 1902). In this triadic relationship there is a scheme of continuity that Peirce calls semiosis, explaining that no interpretant can be seen as absolute or definitive. The sign is mediation for its object and representation for its interpretant. The easiest of those which are of philosophical interest is the idea of a sign, or representation. A 74 sign stands for something to the idea which it produces, or modifies. Or, it is a vehicle conveying into the mind something from without. That for which it stands is called its object; that which it conveys, its meaning; and the idea to which it gives rise, its interpretant. The object of representation can be nothing but a representation of which the first representation is the interpretant. But an endless series of representations, each representing the one behind it, may be conceived to have an absolute object at its limit. The meaning of a representation can be nothing but a representation. In fact, it is nothing but the representation itself conceived as stripped of irrelevant clothing. But this clothing never can be completely stripped off; it is only changed for something more diaphanous. So there is an infinite regression here (CP 1.339, 1875). The typical mode of action of the sign is the growth through selfgeneration. By its own constitution, the sign is bound to germinate and grow, but then comes its inevitably incomplete nature, because the sign is connected to the object, not in all aspects, otherwise it would be the object itself. The otherness of the object is the result of the incompleteness of the sign. The sign can only represent the object and refer to it (CP 2.230, 1910). In Peircean semiotics, the term semiosis refers primarily to the action of the sign to produce an interpretant of itself; but since the interpretant is also a sign with the same sort of productive power, one can speak of the semiosis processes. It should be noted that during the process of semiosis, the generation of the interpretant is primarily more the action of the sign itself than the interpreter (anything that can represent the sign). The role of an interpreter is primarily perception and interpretation. It is also implied a rule according to which the sign is responsible for generating interpretants, that is, an immanent principle that supports the idea that it is an autonomous and self-generative process. A sign is only a sign in actu by virtue of its receiving an interpretation, that is, by virtue of its determining 75 another sign of the same object. This is as true of mental judgments as it is of external signs. To say that a proposition is true is to say that every interpretation of it is true (CP 5.569, 1901). The idea is that the sign has three modal aspects: it has a certain appearance, it is something that occurs or exists, not necessarily in the real world, but in the universe of discourse, and it has the power of generating interpretants. But what logically makes it a sign is the third, which means that we are interested in its power to generate interpretants, that is, a rule that means something that rules. On the other hand, “an argument is always understood by its Interpretant to belong to a general class of analogous arguments, which class, as a whole, tends toward the truth” (CP 2.266, 1903). The operation of the sign is actually the operation of the object through sign (CP 2.277, 1903). The object of the representation is a representation of the first representation which is the interpretant, but an endless series of representations, each representing the previous one, can be conceived as having an absolute object as a limit. Without considering the mathematical concept of limit for Peirce, there is certainly a sense in which the dynamic object is in sequence by virtue of being represented, as long as being the term of a representative relation, it is "ipso facto" part of the sequence, because “to make a distinction between the true conception of a thing and the thing itself is, he will say, only to regard one and the same thing from two different points of view; for the immediate object of thought in a true judgment is the reality”. (CP 8.16, CP 3.482). So, when we realize that Peirce considers thought essentially temporal, it is clear why he says that the immediate object of thought in a true judgment is the reality, the thing in itself as it appears. Thus, “in being real and external, it does not in the least cease to be a purely psychical product, a generalized percept, like everything of which I can take any sort of cognizance” (CP 8.144, 1901). 76 According to Ransdell (2001), semiosis is an interpretative process and therefore has the structure of an objective reference. This structure is implicit and it is not necessarily consciously observed as such. However, to explain the objectivity, it is necessary to understand semiosis, not merely in its formal aspect, but also to develop an understanding of semiosis as a communicative process. Moreover, Ransdell claims that it is implicit in the concept of the interpretant as such, that is, talking about objectivity in a methodical sense is talking about what concerns Peirce in “Fixation of Belief” and "How to make our ideas clear", which is the nature of the research. Since the interpretant represents the relationship between the term sign (relate) and the term object (correlate), it has, by definition, the second intentional function, which means that the logical point of view constitutes the objective consciousness. Peirce asks: what represents sign-thought? What designates it? What is its suppositum? The outward thing, undoubtedly, when a real outward thing is thought of. But still, as the thought is determined by a previous thought of the same object, it only refers to the thing through denoting this previous thought (CP 5.285, 1868). What Peirce describes here as what was previously thought is the immediate object, while the dynamic object is the thing itself regarded as what is "thought of." The theory of interpretants comprises one of the pillars of Peirce's epistemology. The interpretants can be categorized into immediate, dynamic and final. The immediate interpretant is the effect the sign is able to produce. The dynamic interpretant is the effect that the sign actually produces in the interpreter´s mind, it is that what happens in the process of semiosis. The concept of the final interpretant is of utmost importance for the purpose of this work, because Peirce connects it with the truth, “because it is that which would finally be decided to be the true interpretation if consideration of the matter were carried so far that an ultimate opinion were reached” (CP 8.184 n.d.). The final interpretant is the effect that the sign 77 would produce in any mind, a semiosis carried out in the long run, the one that would represent a definitive opinion. The final interpretant is what will appear when we know everything about the object at the end of the investigation, it is the final belief which tends to the evolution of our investigation, the belief that will not be removed. The idea of final interpretant is part of Peirce's cosmology. In the evolutionary process, the final representation would coincide with the object itself, and the final interpretant would coincide with the object itself because the structure of the object would be completely unveiled and the object would not object anymore. If it were possible, in the development of semiosis, to fully reveal the dynamic object that is the real, to the point of fully revealing the dynamic object, then the final interpretant would correspond to the truth. But as the sign produces its interpretants, the dynamic object becomes increasingly complex and the final interpretant (or truth) ends up being continuously postponed. On the other hand, the meaning of an intellectual concept can only be assigned by the study of interpretants, or proper meaning of signs. The first effect is a feeling (emotional interpretant), the second effect is an effort (energetic interpretant), and a third effect is a thought (logical interpretant) (CP 5.475, 1907). From the point of view of logic, the rational meaning of an intellectual concept lies only in the ultimate logical interpretant (habit change), because a sign is interpreted in a subsequent sign, and so ad infinitum (CP 5.492, 1907). “The Truth, the fact that is not abstract but complete, is the ultimate interpretant of every sign”. (NEM IV: 240). In CP 5.56, Peirce claims that truth is in accordance with something that is independent of human thought or opinion (CP 5.211, 1903): That truth is the correspondence of a representation with its object is, as Kant says, merely the nominal definition of it. Truth belongs exclusively to propositions. A proposition has a subject (or set of subjects) and a predicate. The subject is a sign, the predicate is a sign; and the proposition is a sign that the predicate is a sign 78 of that of which the subject is a sign. If it be so, it is true (CP 5.553, 1903). Or, […] In that case, that to which the representation should conform, is itself something in the nature of a representation, or sign — something noumenal, intelligible, conceivable, and utterly unlike a thing-in-itself (CP 5.553, 1903). This passage shows how it is not possible to separate Peirce´s theory of truth from the notions of sign, perception, reality. Truth belongs exclusively to propositions, because in order to make it real it is necessary the action of the object over the sign. Two propositions are equivalent when one of them has been the interpretant of the other, but the interpretant of a proposition and any inference derived from a proposition is an interpretant of it. So when we talk about truth and falsity we refer to the possibility of refuting a proposition: Truth and falsity are characters confined to propositions […] Thus, a false proposition is a proposition of which some interpretant represents that, on an occasion which it indicates, a percept will have a certain character, while the immediate perceptual judgment on that occasion is that the percept has not that character. A true proposition is a proposition belief in which would never lead to such disappointment so long as the proposition is not understood otherwise than it was intended (CP 5.569, 1901). But what does this correspondence or reference of the sign, to its object, consist in? Both the object and the interpretant are integral parts of the sign, as the generation process, which can only be defined in relation to the object and the interpretant. Truth and falsity are properties of representation and contents of representation are vague, indefinite. In order to take over its role as a sign, that is, a sign can only function as a sign if it can be interpreted and this interpretation should be made as another sign (CP 5.553). 79 Your problems would be greatly simplified, if, instead of saying that you want to know the "Truth," you were simply to say that you want to attain a state of belief unassailable by doubt (CP 5.416, 1905). If your terms "truth" and "falsity" are taken in such senses as to be definable in terms of doubt and belief and the course of experience (as for example they would be, if you were to define the "truth" as that to a belief in which belief would tend if it were to tend indefinitely toward absolute fixity), well and good: in that case, you are only talking about doubt and belief (CP 5.416, 1905). 2.1 Truth and Method Logic teaches that Chance, Law and Continuity must be great elements of the explanation of the universe (NEM IV:376). Logic requires us, with reference to each question we have in hand, to hope some defineit answer to it may be true (MS140, NEM IV: xiii). In order to analyze the relationship between truth and method in Peirce's philosophy, it is initially worth emphasizing that Peirce proposes a definition of science as "a mode of life", based on his own experience as a scientist and his knowledge of science history: Science should be a mode of life to us, whose only purpose is to find the truth [...] It does not matter how imperfect the knowledge of a man can be, how subject to error and prejudice, from the moment he engages in an investigation with the spirit described, science is what matters the most (CP 7.54-55 1902). 80 Peirce extends this definition to all sciences. In Peirce´s perspective, when it comes to science in general or in particular, it is understood a community of researchers in a given period of time, with a purpose and a method in common, which makes the result more than a simple sum of individual results. In this context, the socio-historical meaning of a research is clear, which is shown in the following passage: If we are to define science, not in the sense of stuffing it into an artificial pigeon-hole where it may be found again by some insignificant mark, but in the sense of characterizing it as a living historic entity, we must conceive it as that about which such men as I have described busy themselves (CP 1.44 de 1892). So, if a man is thirsty to learn and compare his ideas with experimental results in order to fix these ideas, that man will be recognized by scientists as such, no matter how little his knowledge may be (CP 1.44 de 1892). In Peirce´s research model, presented in his text "Fixation of Belief", research is the struggle for stabilization of belief. The research begins with a doubt, but not Descartes’ doubt, which is a methodological doubt, but a genuine and specific doubt that generates a state of discomfort. From this state of uncomfortable doubt, a scientist, a researcher or even a common person in his everyday life struggles to establish a new belief, which Peirce calls research. We cannot be quite sure that the community ever will settle down to an unalterable conclusion upon any given question. Even if they do so for the most part, we have no reason to think the unanimity will be quite complete, nor can we rationally presume any overwhelming consensus of opinion will be reached upon every question (CP 6.610 de 1891). Therefore, in the method of science, later called pragmatic, our beliefs are determined by something external, independent of our fantasies, and the results we got must meet the reality and also be subjected to the 81 criticism of others. But how does a wide variety of observations and processes can lead to a conclusion that is accepted by all those who understand it? For Peirce, when different researchers agree on a final result, it would not simply be a brute fact; on the contrary, there is convergence of opinions, observations, ideas and viewpoints. The explanation for this is in his theory of reality as the final outcome of the investigation. Reality is not only something that corresponds with the world, but what is represented in the final opinion of the research (CP 1.420, 2.5661, 4.580, 5.453, 5.467, 5.528, 6.327). Rorty (1990: 7) is suspicious of the expression “final opinion”, because he doubts whether this expression can clarify the notions of "absolute truth" and "absolute reality"; he doubts that there is a single project called research that is intended to reach a specific end. Therefore, according to Peirce, research consists of a logical framework and its goal is the knowledge of the real. On the other hand, the belief tends to be gradually set by the influence of the research, that is, in the long run the process of inquiry tends to converge towards the edge and stabilization of belief. Therefore, in Peirce´s writings, there is a conception of truth connected with the establishment or fixation of belief at the end of the research and the scientific method is in the center of this issue. The idea of science as an activity in which a community of researchers is engaged and the conception of reality as a final opinion obtained in the inquiry process can be analyzed as reciprocal. Or, according to Peirce: There is no escaping the admission that the ultimate end of inquiry — the essential, not ulterior end — the mould to which we endeavor to shape our opinions, cannot itself be of the nature of an opinion. Could it be realized, it would rather be like an insistent image, not referring to anything else, and in that sense concrete (CP 8.104, 1900). For Peirce, methods are adopted to minimize surprises and reduce erros (CP 2.173, 6.413). Peirce asks: “Why should one study logic?” 82 In the first place, you would not wish to study logic unless you intended to reason; and you doubtless hold the purpose of reasoning to be the ascertainment of the truth. So it appears that you belong to the sect that maintains that there is such a thing as truth. Ought you not, then, to settle with yourself what that opinion of yours precisely amounts to, and further, what reason there is for entertaining it? In the second place, you not only seem to fancy that there is such a thing as truth, but also that it can be found out and known, in some measure. What reason is there for that? In the third place, you seem to think not only that some knowledge can be attained, but that it can be attained by reasoning. In the fourth place, you seem to think that not only may reasoning lead to the truth, but that a man may be deceived by reasoning badly. This conception seems to demand scrutiny (CP 2.125-128, 1902). Peirce explores the relation between logic and psychology, the nature of truth and reasoning. Peirce describes logic as the art of developing research methods (CP 7:59, 1882), methods that would lead to the truth, because when certain modes of reasoning are persistently met, they should lead us to the truth (CP 1.608, 1903). Scientific research is justified because it is self-correction, which means that on the long run it eliminates errors, because: Thus it is that inquiry of every type, fully carried out, has the vital power of self-correction and of growth. This is a property so deeply saturating its inmost nature that it may truly be said that there is but one thing needful for learning the truth, and that is a hearty and active desire to learn what is true. If you really want to learn the truth, you will, by however 83 devious a path, be surely led into the way of truth, at last. No matter how erroneous your ideas of the method may be at first, you will be forced at length to correct them so long as your activity is moved by that sincere desire. Nay, no matter if you only half desire it, at first, that desire would at length conquer all others, could experience continue long enough. But the more veraciously truth is described at the outset, the shorter by centuries will the road to it be (CP 5.582, 1898). The issue of self-correctiveness is a very controversial topic among scholars Peirce. The argument of self-correctiveness, its relationship with the truth as convergence and the growth of knowledge are addressed by Rescher (1978), Delaney (1993), Hausman (1993) and Misak (1991). To Goudge (1950), the self-correcting tendency is due to the fact that induction is based on samples randomly taken and each sample is free to bring the same frequency, and hence the objective constitution of what is being studied is finally revealed. According to Ransdell (1999), scientific researchers report and respond to each other in accordance with a shared framework of critical expectations, and it is their adherence to ethical standards that makes the process of self-correcting research. In “Scientific Inquiry as a Self-Correcting Process", Foster (n. d.) argues that, when it comes to fixation of beliefs, self-correctiveness of the scientific method would not be only a matter of faith, but it would be at the very superiority of the method over others. The logic of research is seen as a cycle abduction / deduction / induction / new abduction... When surprising events are observed, or differences between predictions and results demand either reformulation or abandonment of the original hypothesis, or the formulation of entirely new hypotheses, then the cycle restarts as new abduction. After proving the validity of abduction, deduction and induction, Peirce shows that together they constitute a method that is self-corrective. The notion of self- 84 correctiveness of science cannot be treated separately from the concept of induction. Forster (n. d.) allocate criticism to self-correctiveness into two groups: the first group comprises those authors who think that Peirce failed to find a successful criterion to defend the scientific method; and the second group comprises those scholars who challenge the adequacy Peirce´s criterion. According to Rescher (1978: 3), Peirce's attempt to justify induction by selfcorrectiveness has been one of the most criticized topics of his philosophy. This self-correcting character, which Peirce calls "wonderful property of Reason", will also be reassured in 1898, in a passage of the Conference "The First Rule of Logic": That Induction tends to correct itself, is obvious enough [...] Now the operation of inferring a law in a succession of observed numbers is, broadly speaking, inductive; and therefore we see that a properly conducted Inductive research corrects its own premises (CP 5.576 or RLT :167, 1898). In the article “The Doctrine of Necessity Examined” (CP 6.50-65, 1892), Peirce develops more fully the defense of the self-correcting character of induction. The self-correction of induction means that in the long run the induction will eventually be successful, and inferences arising from sampling procedures are considered provisional and experiential. Induction is a kind of inference that through continued work will necessarily lead to the truth at the end (CP 2.757, 1905). The self-correctiveness is related to two conditions: sample randomness and pre-selected characters. These two inductive rules generate logical basis for the validity of induction, but they have often been violated (CP 1.95, 1896): The truth is that induction is reasoning from a sample taken at random to the whole lot sampled. A sample is a random one, provided it is drawn by such machinery, artificial or physiological, that in the long run any one individual of the whole lot would get taken as often as any other. 85 Therefore, judging of the statistical composition of a whole lot from a sample is judging by a method which will be right on the average in the long run, and, by the reasoning of the doctrine of chances, will be nearly right oftener than it will be far from right (CP 1.93-94, 1896). For Skagestad (1981:199), there are five things that favor the notion of self-correctiveness: • • • • • the autonomy of pure research, because science is extremely radical, leading us to question accepted theories or doctrines in order to submit them to the test of experience. In this context, Peirce´s conception of truth is crucial, such as the agreement of opinions in the long run; the fallibility of science in the short run. Peirce opposed to positivist ideas, while reinforcing the idea that the validity of induction is based on the calculation of probabilities, which justifies our belief in selfcorrectiveness of induction; Peirce also shows that we cannot trust the results of inductive conclusions; the legitimacy of statistical explanation, based on sample randomness and pre-selected characters; the rejection of Laplace´s theory of probability, that Peirce eventually reduces to absurdity. anthropocentrism of science: this is an important point and is connected to the issue of instinct and the natural tendency of man to formulate correct hypotheses. In “Definitions of Truth” (CP 5.565-573, 1901), Peirce presents many definitions of truth, distinguishing scientific truth from mathematical truth. The pure mathematician deals exclusively with hypotheses, whether or not there is any corresponding real thing is not what we should be concerned with, because hypotheses are created by the imagination. The logical truth is a feature that is linked to an abstract proposition, in the same way that a person can enunciate, it depends essentially that 86 propositions are not expressed as being completely true (CP 5.565, 1901). The truths of mathematics are truths about ideas merely (NEM IV: xv). Peirce also argues that logical truth is a sentence used in three ways: • • • The harmony of a thought with itself. Most usually so defined, but seldom so employed. So far as this definition is distinct, it makes logical truth a synonym for logical possibility; but, no doubt, more is intended. The conformity of a thought to the laws of logic; in particular, in a concept, consistency; in an inference, validity; in a proposition, agreement with assumptions. This would better be called mathematical truth, since mathematics is the only science which aims at nothing more. More properly, the conformity of a proposition with the reality, so far as the proposition asserts anything about the reality. Opposed, on the one hand, to metaphysical truth, which is an affection of the ens, and, on the other hand, to ethical truth, which is telling what a witness believes to be true. (CP 2.541, 1901). But what would Peirce´s criterion of truth be? Apparently, it would be the scientific method itself, because it works when correctly applied. But what is the nature of truth? In the works on logic, from 1873, Peirce begins by asking how a variety of observations and thought processes can lead to a consensual conclusion that is accepted by all the researchers (CP 7331336). The answer would be in the relation truth / reality, in the review of the book "The works of George Berkeley", edited by Fraser (CP 8.7-31 1871). According to Peirce´s realism, real is an object of true opinion. Truth is not an individual matter. The truth has a collective sense and the individual may even lose sight of it, but “it remains that there is a definite opinion to which the mind of man is, on the whole and in the long run, tending” (CP 8.12, 1871). Truth can only be reached in the long run, by the ongoing use of the scientific method and by a scientific community, because there is an outer reality working as a force external to the scientific research, as confirmed in the following passages: A certain writer has suggested that reality, the fact that there is such a thing as a true answer to a 87 question, consists in this: that human inquiries, — human reasoning and observation, — tend toward the settlement of disputes and ultimate agreement in definite conclusions which are independent of the particular stand-points from which the different inquirers may have set out; so that the real is that which any man would believe in, and be ready to act upon, if his investigations were to be pushed sufficiently far (CP 8.41, 1885). It is important to note that it is not a simple idea or a single simple procedure regarding abduction, or deduction, or induction that can achieve correspondence of an idea to reality. Only the full cognitive process, using the correct method of transforming signs, is what makes the truth nothing more or less than the ultimate result we would achieve in case the method had been followed. But even assuming a fallacy may have emerged, we must admit that the only method of reaching the truth is repeating this triad of operations: conjecture (abduction), deduction of predictions from conjecture and test of predictions by experiment (induction) (CP 7.762, 1903). For Peirce, a research is composed of three stages: abduction, deduction and induction, so that it can neither be reduced to any of its parts nor to the hypothetico-deductive method. The scientific method would then be self-corrective as a product of the human mind, which is self-corrective. Thus, the scientific method is itself the criterion of truth, but only in the long term one can tell if the proposition is true. Marostica, (1989: 20-23) examines the development of the scientific method in Peirce´s work, dividing it into three phases. The first phase covers the year 1868 (the anti-Cartesian texts) when Peirce begins to associate the three types of reasoning – deduction, induction and hypothesis- to the scientific method. The second phase corresponds to the period from 1871 to 1878. The scientific method is presented as an effort to calm down the doubt. In "Illustrations of the logic of science", truth is related to method, and probability, to induction. The investigation process can always be restarted and the scientific activity should not be exclusive to a single individual. 88 The third phase corresponds to the development of logic as the method of the methods: The scientific specialists — pendulum swingers and the like — are doing a great and useful work; each one very little, but altogether something vast. But the higher places in science in the coming years are for those who succeed in adapting the methods of one science to the investigation of another. That is what the greatest progress of the passing generation has consisted in. Darwin adapted to biology the methods of Malthus and the economists; Maxwell adapted to the theory of gases the methods of the doctrine of chances, and to electricity the methods of hydrodynamics. Wundt adapts to psychology the methods of physiology; Galton adapts to the same study the methods of the theory of errors; Morgan adapted to history a method from biology; Cournot adapted to political economy the calculus of variations. The philologists have adapted to their science the methods of the decipherers of dispatches. The astronomers have learned the methods of chemistry; radiant heat is investigated with an ear trumpet; the mental temperament is read off on a vernier (CP 7.66, 1898). Mizak (1991: 130-131) relates the objectivity of Peirce's theory with two different explanations of reality. The first is linked to the argument of Fraser's review: "real is that which is not what we eventually think of it, but is not affected by what we might think of it" (CP 8.12, 1871). The second refers to a pragmatic view related to reality that would be this final opinion which is not independent of thought in general, but is independent of all that is arbitrary and individual in thought, that is totally independent of what any number of people may think. Therefore, all you think there is in the final opinion is real, and there is nothing besides that. The idea of truth itself is that it is completely independent of what you or I may think of it. Science is perceived as the best way of knowing the outer world and the induction itself, being ampliative, has a crucial role in the research 89 process, which is to provide the approximate value of an opinion. This was not a viewpoint developed by Peirce later on, because in 1873, he already said: All that we directly experience is our thought — what passes through our minds; and that only, at the moment at which it is passing through. We here see thoughts determining and causing other thoughts, and a chain of reasoning or of association is produced. But the beginning and the end of this chain, are not distinctly perceived. A current is another image under which thought is often spoken of, and perhaps more suitably. We have particularly drawn attention to the point to which thought flows, and that it finally reaches: a certain level, as it were — a certain basin, where reality becomes unchanging. It has reached its destination, and that permanency, that fixed reality, which every thought strives to represent and image, we have placed in this objective point, towards which the current of thought flows (CP 7.337, 1873). However, from 1980 on, Peirce starts to insist that truth would be what the scientific community would find if it carried out an ongoing research, introducing the would-be´s. But above all things it is the searching thoroughness of the schoolmen which affiliates them with men of science and separates them, world-wide, from modern so-called philosophers. The thoroughness I allude to consists in this, that in adopting any theory, they go about everywhere, they devote their whole energies and lives in putting it to tests bona fide — not such as shall merely add a new spangle to the glitter of their proofs but such as shall really go toward satisfying their restless insatiable impulse to put their opinions to the test. Having a theory, they must apply it to every subject and to every branch of every subject to see whether it produces a result in accordance with the only criteria they were able to 90 apply — the truth of the Catholic faith and the teaching of the Prince of Philosophers (CP 1.33, 1869). This paragraph highlights that people seek science driven by an interest in achieving true knowledge of things. They are attracted by the truth as one of the aspects of summum bonum. And the lure of the truth over the scientific community is one aspect of agapism that attracts everything in the evolutionary process, because a scientist must be particularly honest with himself, “otherwise, his love of truth will melt away, at once” (CP 1.49, 1896). Thus, assuming that the truth is something that thought can reach, and that thought is in the nature of the sign, then if we can figure out a correct way of thinking – the correct method of transforming signs - then truth cannot be nothing less than the ultimate result we would be taken to when following this method (CP 5553, 1902). Peirce highlights the temporary feature of scientific truths: Nothing is vital for science; nothing can be. Its accepted propositions, therefore, are but opinions at most; and the whole list is provisional. The scientific man is not in the least wedded to his conclusions. He risks nothing upon them. He stands ready to abandon one or all as soon as experience opposes them (CP 1.635-36, 1898). 2.2 Truth and Pragmatism Supposing such a thing to be true, what is the kind of proof which I ought to demand to satisfy me of its truth? (CP 2.112) Peirce has always wanted to rid philosophy of metaphysics tautology to bring it as close as possible to the methods of the natural sciences (CP 5.423 or CP 5.2, 1901). His interest in finding a maxim that was clear and easy to understand led him to formulate pragmatism, which 91 has always been described as a reflection method whose only purpose is to bring clarity to ideas. The increasing popularity of pragmatism led Peirce to produce “evidence”, that is, to show that pragmaticism is "probable, it is not only a maxim" (CP 5.415, 1904) and this "evidence" would distinguish his version of pragmatism from other versions. According to Peirce, what distinguishes his pragmatism from others is “first, its retention of a purified philosophy; secondly, its full acceptance of the main body of our instinctive beliefs; and thirdly, its strenuous insistence upon the truth of scholastic realism” (CP 5.423 de 1905). Hookway (2003) argues that Peirce considered his version of pragmatism different from the others because it could be proved. He made his first attempt in 1898, but the search for this evidence would become the center of his work after 1900. In the evolution of Peirce's thought, the interrelationship of normative sciences is made clear from 1905 on. Also, from this period on, Peirce begins to use the conditional would be in the new versions of the pragmatic maxims, which makes pragmatism the right method of transforming signs, with the goal of achieving the ultimate result, the truth. In 1905, Peirce states that “it is the right time to explain what pragmatism is.” Pragmatism is “in itself, no doctrine of metaphysics, no attempt to determine any truth of things. “It is merely a method of ascertaining the meanings of hard words and of abstract concepts” (CP 5.464, 1905). Peirce claims that pragmatism is a “method to confirm meaning”, but not all ideas, “only of what I call ‘intellectual concepts’, that is to say, of those upon the structure of which, arguments concerning objective fact may hinge”. Pragmatism becomes a linking point of many aspects that were partially disconnected in Peirce's philosophy, including the theory of signs, the theory of investigation and pragmatism itself. Thus, in the context of pragmatism, Peirce will revise his theory of belief, centered on the concept of habit, and will resume the theory of signs with special emphasis on the 92 interpretants. Also, the works that Peirce produced between 1901 and 1903 should be considered, including a proposal developed for Carnegie Institution, in which Peirce asked for financial support for his projects on logic, namely Minute Logic, which would show his main discoveries in continuity and modality. The development of a new theory of perception on the basis of phenomenology and the examination of the interrelationship of normative sciences will lead Peirce to reformulate pragmatism as a doctrine in which the concepts are not related to the action, but the ultimate goal, the summum bonum. The ultimate goal of action deliberately adopted, that is, reasonably adopted, "must be an admirable ideal" (CP 5.130, 1903). I also want to say that after all pragmatism solves no real problem. It only shows that supposed problems are not real problems. But when one comes to such questions as immortality, the nature of the connection of mind and matter (further than that mind acts on matter not like a cause but like a law) we are left completely in the dark. The effect of pragmatism here is simply to open our minds to receiving any evidence, not to furnish evidence. (CP 8.259, 1902). Pragmatism is a step in the general procedure of synechism, because the correct formulation of hypotheses presupposes a correct understanding of the concepts employed as well, but both synechism and pragmatism are built from realism, because everything rests on the assumption that there are general reals (CP 5.503, 1905). It is worth noting that assuming a satisfactory attitude towards the element of Thirdness is what later would be the pragmatic criterion (CP 5.206, 1903). Pragmatism, therefore, reinforces the general character of realism through the would-be's because “Pragmaticism consists in holding that the purport of any concept is its conceived bearing upon our conduct” (CP 5.460, 1905), that is, the reality of generals is the reality of would-be’s. Pragmatism is the principle that every theoretical judgment expressible in a sentence in the indicative mood is a confused form of thought whose only meaning, if it has any, lies in its tendency to enforce 93 a corresponding practical maxim expressible as a conditional sentence having its apodosis in the imperative mood (CP 5.18). The applicability of the criterion of truth demands the criterion of meaning, which is pragmatism itself. From the notion of reality and research, Pragmatism emerges as a method of verification of our general conceptions: Pragmatism is the key method to know and determine the meaning of these persistent realities that force themselves upon our recognition. That which has no such persistence is just a dream, and reality is persistent, it is regular (CP 1.175, 1897). Pragmatism is equivalent to the basic procedures of the laboratory sciences, but can be employed in any field of knowledge, because for Peirce Pragmatism is the method of methods, the method of the other methods, a method of acquiring and developing knowledge of universal scope. Its triple framework can be defined as problem identification (problems are those turbulent experiences or misunderstanding of reality, that is, those moments when our core beliefs do not correspond to reality, which demand of us the understanding that our knowledge is fallible and subject to error), elaboration of explanatory hypotheses and hypotheses test for later disposal of those that have no explanatory power. The remaining hypotheses will be inductively tested, in order to provide likely and reliable results. The elimination of a hypothesis means that this hypothesis or its predictive explanation is inconsistent or contradictory in relation to what it was supposed to explain. On the other hand, realism, one of the main topics supported by Peirce, is fundamental to our understanding, so that any problem that needs to be solved presents two major issues: • • whether the initial theory or set of beliefs remains the same at the time of testing if the hypothetical solution explains our problem or not It is important to observe that each exercise of pragmatic experimentation, however simple or sophisticated, implies that there was a certain basic sense of reality, a certain theory about what the world is made of and how it behaves, a set of beliefs about what we think and how we 94 know. We can improve or increase our knowledge through appropriate information, correct reasoning and creative approach. However, the reality does not change, we cannot fix it, because real remains indifferent to our wanderings or selfishness (CP 5.111, 1903). Abduction, deduction and induction are closely involved with the pragmatic experimental process of acquisition and development of knowledge, considering the connections between the structure of our initial problem of formulating and testing hypotheses and Peirce´s architecture and logic. If induction and probability describe knowledge as a movement towards the future, deduction and logic need guide us through the process of eliminating failed hypotheses, abduction can be considered a form of reasoning that leads us to recognize the problem. In Peirce, what primarily matters in order to support a claim based on the inductive method is not just a successful prediction of facts, but also that they can be classified as typical, that is, they are random specimens of all predictions that could be based on the hypothesis and constitute the axis of truth. Pragmatism was originally conceived not to abandon concepts such as true or right, but clarify and elucidate them. Rorty (1982: xiv) argues that pragmatism suggests that we do not ask questions about the nature of truth or goodness, so from this point of view, pragmatism does not constitute a philosophical doctrine, but a position that recommends the abandonment of philosophy in search for something else. If we adopt Rorty´s view, one of the key issues of philosophy, which refers to those considerations that support our beliefs and choices, should be abandoned. Rescher (2000: xii) believes that pragmatism is not anti-skepticism but a rational approach to solve theoretical problems, considering our practical and cognitive obligations. In the hands of its founder, Peirce, pragmatism had two main components, one concerning the meaning and another related to the truth. For Peirce, the crucial point of pragmatism is something conditional, that is, there is an established research methodology - the scientific method - that, when used with persistence, in an ongoing community of rational researchers, must produce the truth in the end. 95 Murphy (1990: 39-55) points out nine fundamental principles of Peirce´s pragmatism, namely: • Beliefs are identical if and only if they give rise to the same habit of action • Beliefs give rise to the same habit of action only if they appease the same doubt by producing the same rule of action • The meaning of a thought is the belief it produces • Beliefs produce the same rule of action if they lead us to act in the same sensible situations • There is no distinction of meaning so fine as to consist in anything but a possible difference in what is tangible and conceivably practical • Our idea of anything is our idea of its sensible effects • Considering what effects might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive what the object of our conception has. Then our conception of these effects is our whole conception of the object • A true belief is one which is fated to be ultimately agreed to by all who investigate scientifically • Any object represented in a true opinion is real On the other hand, pragmatism is usually associated with the idea of truth. William James himself defined his pragmatism as a theory of truth. According to Rescher (2000:13), pragmatism has three forms: semantic pragmatism: the meaning of terms consists on their use, epistemic pragmatism: the successful implementation of beliefs is the proper criterion for their truth, and ontological pragmatism (or metaphysical): in the human realm, praxis has primacy over theory because all understanding must itself be the product of a doing. In Rescher´s view (2000), Peirce supported all three doctrines, but the latter would become particularly "portentuous" for him, because all human activity can always be refined, extended, and improved, which 96 means that our knowledge of the truth is always experimental and imperfect, and it was this line of thought that led Peirce to fallibilism. Only in an idealized long term, our pragmatically validated knowledge can be considered the truth as such. Peirce related the truth with what an intelligent community of scientific researchers actually thinks about the issue, not here and now, but in the distant, indefinite future, the theoretical long term. The problem is that the natural course of observation never reaches this idealized long term, no matter how it is understood, it is beyond our cognitive reach (Rescher, 2000). Truth is the conformity of a representation to its object, but what is the object used to define truth? It is reality, whose nature is so independent of its representations that, by taking any single sign or any individual collection of signs, there is a character to which the thing belongs (CP 1.578, 1902). Therefore, for Peirce, truth is objective, because there is such a thing as truth, because otherwise reasoning and thought would not have a purpose. Peirce asks: What do you mean by such a thing as truth? For Peirce, the essence of truth lies in its resistance to being ignored (CP 2.139, 1902), because we deceive ourselves, but we all have had some experience of reacting against something, Besides, say those who object to this method, all reasoning and inquiry expects that there is such a thing as the truth concerning whatever question may be under examination. Now, it is of the very essence of this "truth," the meaning of the expectation, that the "truth" in no wise depends upon what any man to whom direct appeal can be made may opine about that question. (CP 2.209, 1901). Truth is public, truth is truth, whether it is opposed to the interests of society to admit it or not (CP 8.143, 1901). Even though researchers seek a position of stable belief, there is no guarantee that this position will be achieved and that it is not threatened by new facts that raise questions that 97 need to be explained and lead to new investigations. But in the long run we could reach a state of belief unassailable by doubt, which Peirce called truth. Pragmatism is a method of determining the meaning of intellectual concepts, so pragmatism is the right method of transforming signs whose objective is to obtain the logical good, and consequently the truth. The pragmatic characterization of truth joins truth and research, and consequently method. It is therefore the pragmatic method that generates this version of the truth, which according to Misak (1991: 160) has three advantages: first, it provides a rational context for the research to be conducted; second, the pursuit of truth becomes the goal of research practice; and third, Peirce´s theory of truth provides and justifies a methodology that uses the scientific method of abduction, deduction and induction, and applies the pragmatic criterion of legitimacy of hypotheses. Truth then becomes something we aim to investigate. It can be said that in the logic of scientific research, reality would be constituted through signs, because "we can only indicate the real universe; if we are asked to describe it, we can only say that it includes whatever there might be in what it really is". This is universal, not individual (CP 8.208). The concept of truth can be analyzed from the point of view of interpretants and research. The concept of truth that comes from that fixed belief in the hypothetical end of the investigation depends on the realism of the conditionals (would- be's) and these conditionals need the collaboration of interpretants, especially the definition of the ultimate logical interpretant. We have indexes of the outer world. These indexes bring in themselves the generality of reality, because they derive from general principles operating in nature, that is, through logical consequences of signs, and pragmatism is the right method of transforming signs with the purpose of reaching the ultimate result, truth, which is the view that will be established and settled after enough research (MS 300, 1905). 98 Final Considerations Throughout this paper, we aimed to present two themes of Peirce, his realism and his theory of truth. In Part I, we tried to show some aspects of the realism-antirealism debate in order to describe the assumptions of Peirce's realism. Peirce supports the objectivity of knowledge, according to which the possibility of an ultimate answer to every question derives from the existence of real. The fact that the real is not affected by what we think, that the real is independent of what one may think of it, and that a community of researchers, using a correct method, will reach an opinion with which all agree with, emerge his theory of reality, his theory of knowledge, which will be the pillars of the scientific method, which bring in its core the realism and the theory of truth. For Peirce, the notion of reality has two important aspects: the otherness that characterizes the element that reacts (associated with Secondness, category of existence), and the insistence of brute force, which enables knowledge by maintaining certain regularity (associated with Thirdness, what is the category of generality, the law). Peirce´s realism can be classified as one of three categories, by acceptance of reality as Firstness, Secondness and Thirdness, realism by accepting the reality of Firstness, Secondness and Thirdness, through awareness that human rationality is a continuum of rationality of the universe, as part of the doctrine of synechism, but subject to the action of chance (tychism), seeking an ideal in its development, from the interrelationship of the normative sciences, according to which pragmatism becomes a doctrine in which the concepts are not related to the action, but to the summum bonum, or admirable. Peirce´s realism implies not only a consideration of a real object, independent of the outer world, but a recognition of the reality of universals in contrast to nominalism, to which the continuum is only a matter of language. For nominalists, universals are just signs created to designate the quality of particular things. Nominalists refuse an objective correspondence of our concepts with the laws of nature, so realism implies objectivity of the laws of nature. 99 In Part II, it was initially presented a contextualization of the main theories of truth as a background for the analysis of Peirce's theory of truth. For Peirce, the truth is public and anyone that carried out a research and used the correct method would come to it. Truth and reality are related concepts. Peirce supports scientific research as a path to the truth. This work was developed based on the triadic semiotic relationship among sign, object and interpretant. From the relationship between the sign and its object, in which Secondness, opposition, otherness, and determination prevails, results one the aspects of his realism. From the relationship between the sign and the interpretant, as mediation or interpretation, we can understand the action of the sign as semiosis, such as continuity, but that is subject to indeterminacy, fate, freedom. Thus, it will be through the convergence of interpretants that the research community will come to the truth in the long run, if this process is guided by a purpose, the summum bonum. 100 References Almeder, R. (1985).Thirteen Theories of Truth. Transactions of The Charles S. Peirce Society. vol. XXI, n.1, pp.77-94. Altshuler, B. (1982) Peirce´s Theory of Truth and the Revolt against Realism. Transactions of The Charles S. Peirce Society. vol. XVIII, n.1, pp. 34-56. Bacha, ML. (1998). A teoria da Investigação de C. S. Peirce. São Paulo: CenaUm. Bacha, ML. (2002). A Indução de Aristóteles a Peirce. São Paulo: Legnar Informática & Editora. Besusan, H. (1994). O argumento de milagre e a explicação do sucesso da ciência. (Dissertação de Mestrado). Universidade de São Paulo, Brasil. Blackburn, S., & Simmons, K. (1999). Truth. New York: Oxford University Press Inc. Boyd, R. (1991). On the Current Status of Scientific Realism. In R. Boyd, P. Gasper, & J. D. Trout. The philosophy of science (pp 195-222) Cambridge: MIT Press. Bradley, F.H. (1999). On Truth and Copying, In Blackburn, S., & Simmons, K. (1999). Truth. New York: Oxford University Press Inc. Carrilho, M (1990). Verdade, Suspeita e Argumentação. Lisboa: Ed. Presença. Chauí, M. (1994). Convite à Filosofia. São Paulo Ática. Da Costa, N. (1980). Ensaio sobre os fundamentos da Lógica. São Paulo: Edusp. Da Costa, N. (1993). Lógica Indutiva e Probabilidade. São Paulo: UNESP. Da Costa, N. (1997). O Conhecimento Científico. São Paulo: Fapesp/ Discurso editorial. 101 Davidson, D (1990 june). The Structure and Content of Truth. The Journal of Philosophy, vol. LXXXVII, n. 6. Davidson, D (1999). Truth, meaning.and knowledge. London and New York: Routledge. Davidson, D. (2002). A verdade é o objetivo da investigação? – discussão com Rorty, Translated by Paulo Ghiraldelli Jr. Available from: http://filosofia.pro.br/gt-prgmatismo/gt-pragmatismo.htm, Data downloaded in April 23, 2002. Deely, J. (1994). New Beginnings - Early Modern Philosphy and Post Modern Thought. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Delaney, C.F. (1993). Science, Knowledge and Mind - A Study in the Philosophy of C. S. Peirce. Notre Dame/London: University of Notre Dame Press. Descartes, R. (1996). O discurso do método. (col. Pensadores). São Paulo: Ed. Abril, vol.IX, p.61/127. Dummett, M. (1978). Truth and Other Enigmas. London: Duckworth. Fine, A. (1986). The Shaky Game. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Fine, A. (1991). The Natural Ontological Attitude, in In R. Boyd, P. Gasper, & J.D. Trout. The philosophy of science (pp 171-186) Cambridge: MIT Press. Forster, P (s.d.) Scientific Inquiry as a Self-Correcting Process. Available from http://members.door.net/arisbe/menu/library/aboutcsp/ aboutcsp.htm. Forster, P. (1989). Peirce on the Progress and Authority of Science. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, vol. XXV, n.4, pp. 421-452. Forster, P. (1997). The Logical Foundations of Peirce’s Indeterminism. In J. Brunning, & P. Forster (ed). The Rule of Reason, The Philosophy of 102 Charles Sanders Peirce (pp 57-81). Toronto/Buffalo/ London: University of Toronto Press. Forster, P., & J. Brunning. (1997). Introduction. In J. Brunning, & P. Forster (ed). The Rule of Reason, The Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce (pp ). Toronto/Buffalo/ London: University of Toronto Press. Gadamer, H. (2002) Verdade e Método II. Translated Ênio Paulo Giachini; Petrópolis, RJ: Ed. Vozes. Goodman, N. (1983). Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. London: Harvard University Press. Haack, S. (1978) Philosophy of Logics, Cambridge: University Press. Haack, S. (1992). Extreme Scholastic Realism: Its Relevance to Philosophy of Science Today. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, vol. XXVIII, n.1, pp.19-50. Haack, S. (1997). The First Rule of Reason. In J. Brunning, & P. Forster (ed). The Rule of Reason, The Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce (pp.241-262). Toronto/Buffalo/ London: University of Toronto Press. Haack, S. (1998). Manifesto of a Passionate Moderate. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Haack, S. (2001). Filosofia das Lógicas. São Paulo: Unesp. Hausman, C. R. (1986). Peirce´s Evolutionary Realism. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, vol. XXII, n.3, pp. 475-500. Hausman, C. R. (1990). In and Out of Peirce’s Percepts. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, vol. XXVI, no. 3, pp. 271-309. Hausman, C. R. (1993). Charles S. Peirce’s Evolutionary Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press. Hildebrand, D. L. (2003). Beyond Realism and Antirealism: John Dewey and the Neopragmatists. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press. 103 Hilpinen, R. (1992). On Peirce's Philosophical Logic: Propositions and Their Objects. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 28 (3):467 488. Hookway, C. (1992). Peirce. London and New York: Routledge & Kegan. Hookway, C. (1993). Belief, Confidence and the Method of Science, Transactions of The Charles S. Peirce Society, vol. XXIX, no. 1, pp.1-32. Hookway, C. (1997). Sentiment and Self-Control. In J. Brunning, & P. Forster (ed). The Rule of Reason, The Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce (pp.201-222) Toronto/Buffalo/ London: University of Toronto Press. Hookway, C. (2003) Truth, Rationality, and Pragmatism: Themes from Peirce, New York; Oxford University Press. Horwich, P. (1996). Realism and Truth, Philosophical Perspectives, Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives, Metaphysics, n. 10. Source: Noûs, Vol. 30, 10, Metaphysics, pp. 187-197 Horwich, P. (1998). Truth. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Horwich, P. (2010). Truth – Meaning - Reality. New York: Oxford University Press. Houser, N. (1983). Peirce’s General Taxonomy of Consciounes. Transactions of The Charles S. Peirce Society, vol. XIX, n. pp.331359. Houser, N. (1986). Introduction. In by the Peirce Project (ed.) The Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition. Vol. 4. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Houser, N. (1992). O Escopo da Semiótica Peirceana. Face-Revista de Semiótica e Comunicação, vol.3, n.2. Houser, N. (1997). Introduction: Peirce as Logician. In N. Houser, D. Roberts, & J. van Evra (ed). Studies of The Logic of Charles 104 Sanders Peirce (pp 1-22). Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. Houser, N. (1998). Introduction. In The Peirce Edition Project (ed). The Essential Peirce (pp.xix-xli). Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Joachim, H.H. The Nature of Truth, in Blackburn, S., & Simmons, K. (1999). Truth. New York: Oxford University Press Inc. Kirkham, R. L. (1995). Theories of Truth – A Critical Introduction. Massachusetts: MIT Press. Levi, I. (1980). The Enterprise of Knowledge: An Essay on Knowledge, Credal Probability, and Chance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1980. Marostica, A H. (1989). Peirce´s conception of truth - a tychist approach, (Doctoral dissertation). Indiana University, Bloomington, USA. Misak, C.J. (1991). Truth and the End of Inquiry: a Peircean Account of Truth. New York: At the Clarendon Press. Murphy, J. (1990). O Pragmatismo de Peirce a Davidson, Porto: Ed. ASA. Musgrave, A. (1998). Common Sense, Science and Scepticism, A historical introduction to the theory of knowledge. London: Cambridge University Press. Peirce, C. S. (1931-35). Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Ed. by Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss, Vols.1-6, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. Peirce, C. S. (1958). Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Ed. by Arthur Burks. Vols 7 - 8. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. Peirce, C. S. (1976). The New Elements of Mathematics by Charles S. Peirce .Ed Carolyn Eisele. The Hague: Mouton, 4 vols. Peirce, C. S. (1982). Wrintings of Charles S.Peirce: A Chronological Edition. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, vol I: 1857-1866. 105 Peirce, C. S. (1984). Wrintings of Charles S.Peirce: A Chronological Edition. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. vol.II: 1867-1871. Peirce, C. S. (1985). Historical Perspectives on Peirce's Logic of Science. Ed. Carolyn Eisele. Berlin/ New York/ Amsterdam: Mouton, 2 vols. Peirce, C. S. (1986). Wrintings of Charles S.Peirce: A Chronological Edition. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, vol III: 1872-1878. Peirce, C. S. (1986). Wrintings of Charles S.Peirce: A Chronological Edition. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, vol IV: 1879-1884. Peirce, C. S. (1992). Reasoning and the Logic of Things. Ed. Kenneth Laine Ketner, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. Peirce, C. S. (1992). The Essential Peirce. Ed. by Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Peirce, C. S. (1993). Wrintings of Charles S.Peirce: A Chronological Edition. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, vol v: 1884-1886. Peirce, C. S. (1998). The Essential Peirce. Ed. by The Peirce Edition Project, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. vol. 2. Plastino, C. (1995). Realismo e antirealismo acerca da ciência. (Tese de Doutoramento). Universidade de São Paulo, Brasil. Plastino, C. (2000). A verdade como Limite Ideal. Cognitio Revista de Filosofia, ano 1, n. 1, pp. 86-93. Plastino, C. (2000). Indução e Credibilidade. Ciência & Filosofia, n. 6, pp.760. Plastino, C. (2000). Realismo Metafísico e Relatividade conceitual. Cognitio Revista de Filosofia, ano 1, n. 1, pp. 79-85 Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific Realism- how science tracks truth. New York: Routledge. Putnam, H. (1991). Explanation and Reference. In R. Boyd, P. Gasper, & J.D. Trout. The philosophy of science (pp 171-186) Cambridge: MIT Press. 106 Putnam, H. (1995). Pragmatism – an open question. Oxford: Blackwell. Putnan, H., & Putnan, R. A. (1990). Epistemology as Hypothesis. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, vol. XXVI, n.4, pp.407-441. Quine, W. V. (1995). “Cinco Marcos do Empirismo”. Filosofia e Filosofia da Educação, http://filosofia.pro/textos/.html Quine, W. V. (1995). Filosofia e linguagem. Porto: Edições ASA. Quine, W. V. 0. (1991). Natural Kinds. In R. Boyd, P. Gasper, & J.D. Trout. The philosophy of science (pp.159-170) Cambridge: MIT Press. Ramsey, F.P. (1999). On Facts and Propositons, in Blackburn, S., & Simmons, K. (1999). Truth. New York: Oxford University Press Inc. Ransdell, J. (1999). Ransdell’s response to the APS definition of science. Internet: Available from: gopher://gopher.ttu.edu:70/0R157558187909-/Pubs/peirce/peirce-l/9905 Ransdell, J. (2001). Peirce´s Immediate/dynamical object distinction and the solution of the problem of representative perception. Texto inédito cedido pelo autor. Rescher, N (1994). Philosophical Standardism-an empirical approach to philosophical methodology. Pittisburgh: University of Pittisburgh Press. Rescher, N. (2000). Realistic Pragmatism - an introduction to pragmatic philosophy. New York: State of University of New York Press. Rescher, N. (2005). Pragmatism at the Crossroads.Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. vol. 41 Issue 2, p355-365. 11p. Rorty, R. (1967). The Linguistic Turn. Chicago: The University of Chigaco Press. Rorty, R. (1982). Consequences of Pragmatism. Mineapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Rorty, R. (1990). O Pragmatismo de Peirce a Davidson. Porto: Ed. ASA. 107 Rorty, R. (1994). A Filosofia e o Espelho da Natureza. Rio de Janeiro: Belume Dumará. Rorty, R. (1999) Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers. London: Cambridge University Press. Rorty, R. (2003) Consequences of Pragmatism, Essays: 1972-1980, Minneapolis: University of Press. Rosenthal, S. (1983). The Pragmatic World of Charles Peirce, Transactions of The Charles S.Peirce Society, vol. XIX, n.1, pp.13-22. Rosenthal, S. (2001), The Percipuum and the Issue of Foundations Commens, Digital Companion to C. S. Peirce, available from http://www.commens.org/encyclopedia/article/rosenthal-sandrapercipuum-and-issue-foundations. Russell, B. (1945). History of Western Philosophy. New York: Simon and Schuster. Russell, B. (1962). A Perspectiva Científica. São Paulo: Companhia Editora Nacional. Santaella, L. (1993). Metodologia Semiótica. Fundamentos. (Tese de Livre Docência). Universidade de São Paulo, Brasil. Savan, D. (1964) Peirce's infallibilism. In Moore, E., and Robin, R.S. (1964), Studies in the Philosophy of C.S. Peirce, Second Series, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, MA. Scheffer, I. (1994). Induction Inference: A New Approach. Grue! The new riddle of Induction. Chicago and LaSalle, Illinois: Open Court. Searle, J. R. (1993) The Problem of Consciousness, Social Research: An International Quarterly,Volume 59, No. 4 (Winter 1993): 3:16. Skagestad, P. (1981). The Road Of Inquiry - Charles Peirce's Pragmatic Realism. New York: Columbia University Press. Skagestad, P. (2002). Os primeiros passos rumo à verdade, Cognitio, Revista de Filosofia, Centro de Estudos do Pragmatismo, Filosofia, PUC, SP, n.3, nov., pp.107-114. 108 Souza, E.G. (2000). O conceito de verdade pragmática em um perspectiva lógico-formal, Cognitio Revista de Filosofia, ano 1, n.1, pp.138-144. Strawson, F. S. (1950) Truth, SUPPLEMENTARY VOLUME XXIV, avaliable from http://www.aristoteliansociety.org.uk/pdf/strawson.pdf. Tarski, A. (1991). Verdade e demonstração. Caderno de História e Filosofia da Ciência. série 3, v.1, pp. 90-121. Thompson, M. (1952) The Pragmatic Philosophy of C. S. Peirce. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Van Fraassen, B. (1989) Laws and Symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Van Fraassen, B. (1991) To Save the Phenomena. In: The philosophy of science / edited by Richard Boyd, Philip Gasper, and J.D. Trout. Cambridge: MIT Press.