06.04.2015 Views

Process Studies Supplement Overcoming Anthropocentric ... - Here

Process Studies Supplement Overcoming Anthropocentric ... - Here

Process Studies Supplement Overcoming Anthropocentric ... - Here

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Process</strong> <strong>Studies</strong> <strong>Supplement</strong><br />

Issue 12 (2008)<br />

<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

and Radical Anti-Humanism: Contours<br />

of the Constructive Postmodernist<br />

Environmental Epistemology<br />

Adam C. Scarfe, Ph.D., M.Ed.<br />

Department of Philosophy and Religious <strong>Studies</strong>, California State University,<br />

Bakersfield, Faculty Towers 101-D, 9001 Stockdale Hwy, Bakersfield,<br />

California, 93311 U.S.A. E-mail: .<br />

Abstract: Drawing on eco-psychology’s central problematic concerning the<br />

assumed conceptual bifurcation between the human self and the natural<br />

world, which is prevalent in contemporary modern culture, this paper explores<br />

the main contours of constructive postmodernist environmental epistemology,<br />

as exemplified by Alfred North Whitehead’s process-relational thought. With<br />

reference to characterizations of the modern and deconstructive postmodern<br />

paradigms derived from Sartre’s existentialism and Derrida’s deconstructionism,<br />

it sets forth a novel demonstration of how Whitehead’s process-relational<br />

way of thinking, as representative of a critical, non-anthropocentric organicism,<br />

overcomes both the anthropocentric humanist assumptions of the<br />

modern paradigm, which are at the root of the ecological crisis, as well as the<br />

anti-humanism common to both deconstructive postmodernism and radical<br />

ecologism. I show how process-relational environmental epistemology can<br />

contribute to the cultivation of a heightened awareness of the prehensive<br />

character of human experience in our culture, by which the human self is, in<br />

part, constituted, with a concern to limit the rate and extent of the appropriation,<br />

consumption, and destruction of “the natural” belonging to many forms<br />

of human creativity, thereby tempering the “attack on the environment” via<br />

reasoned self-limitation. At the same time, I point out that process-relational<br />

environmental epistemology seeks to allow for sustainable levels of development,<br />

human creativity, life-satisfaction, and self-enjoyment.


2<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

Toward an outline of the contours of “process-relational”<br />

environmental epistemology<br />

In responding to the overwhelming scientific consensus that there is a<br />

causal connection between various human activities (e.g., the burning<br />

of fossil fuels) and environmental problems (e.g., climate change), the<br />

philosopher’s task is to reflect on, to identify, and to take issue with ways<br />

of thinking which are at the root of such environmentally destructive<br />

activities. This philosophical stream of inquiry may be called environmental<br />

epistemology, the results of which lead logically into the domain<br />

of ethics, precisely, into considerations of what sorts of behavior and<br />

ways of life are authentically constitutive of environmentally ethical<br />

praxis and how they contrast with those which contribute to the worsening<br />

of such ecological dysfunctions. One major issue in environmental<br />

epistemology, which it is the purpose of this paper to examine from a<br />

process-relational standpoint, is to identify what is problematic with<br />

present assumptions concerning the way human beings think about the<br />

relationship (or lack thereof) between themselves and the natural world,<br />

in order to then move toward considering how human beings ought to<br />

conceive of it. Therefore, environmental epistemology is both descriptive<br />

as well as prescriptive. 1 That said, environmental epistemology does not<br />

subjectively “cater the truth” to the specific circumstance of the ecological<br />

crisis. Rather, the very fact that there is an ecological crisis, to begin<br />

with, exemplifies the dominance of false and problematic assumptions<br />

regarding the relationship between the human self and the natural world<br />

in contemporary culture.<br />

<strong>Here</strong>, drawing on eco-psychology’s problematic concerning the<br />

relationship between the human self and the natural world, Sartre’s existentialism<br />

and Derrida’s deconstructionism, the present essay serves, more<br />

generally, to outline some of the main contours of the environmental epistemology<br />

which emerges out of Whiteheadian, process-relational modes of<br />

thought, the latter representative of an alternative form of postmodernism,<br />

namely, a “constructive” or more accurately, “re-constructive postmodernism”<br />

(Griffin, “Introduction” xii). Specifically, I intend to set forth a<br />

novel demonstration of how Alfred North Whitehead’s process-relational<br />

way of thinking, characterized as a critical, non-anthropocentric organicism,<br />

overcomes both the anthropocentric humanist assumptions of the<br />

modern paradigm, which are at the root of the ecological crisis, as well as


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism 3<br />

the anti-humanism common to both deconstructive postmodernism and<br />

radical ecologism. In order to carry out this task, it will first be necessary to<br />

provide a brief analysis of some of the main themes of eco-psychology in<br />

raising the epistemological problem of the conceptual bifurcation between<br />

the human self and the natural world. Second, I shall demonstrate how<br />

Sartre’s characterization of the fundamental project of human-reality in<br />

Being and Nothingness illuminates the underlying meaning of substantialist<br />

conceptions of the human self and Nature, as well as of the anthropocentric<br />

humanism of the modern paradigm. Third, it will be imperative to<br />

provide a brief synopsis of Derrida’s deconstructionism, with reference<br />

to his critique of anthropocentric humanism in the essay, “The Ends of<br />

Man” as well as of his allegations concerning Sartre’s complicity with it.<br />

Fourth, it will be necessary to elaborate on some of the anti-humanist<br />

affinities between deconstructive postmodernism and radical ecologism.<br />

Fifth, I shall show how the Whiteheadian process-relational environmental<br />

epistemology presents a critical, non-anthropocentric organicism that<br />

overcomes the vicious dichotomy between the anthropocentric humanism<br />

of the “modern” paradigm and the extreme anti-humanism of both<br />

“deconstructive postmodernism” and radical ecologism.<br />

Eco-psychology’s critique of the conceptual bifurcation of<br />

the human self from the natural world<br />

Eco-psychology is one of several fairly recent ecological movements arising<br />

from within the social scientific discipline of psychology; although it is<br />

constituted by an attempt to critically reassess the latter’s basic assumptions.<br />

Other critical environmentally engaged forms of psychology include<br />

ecological psychology, conservation psychology, psycho-ecology, and terrapsychology.<br />

2 Coinciding with other environmental movements, such as<br />

deep ecology, ecozoicism, and eco-feminism, eco-psychology maintains<br />

that consciousness of the plight of the natural environment needs to be<br />

developed not solely on the basis of the notion that the ecological crisis is a<br />

threat to human survival, but in that the natural world has value-in-itself. Its<br />

main aim is to overcome the anthropocentrism which is at the root of the<br />

environmental crisis. Particularly, eco-psychologists, such as Andy Fisher,<br />

David Kidner, and Theodore Roszak, criticize the anthropocentric, “ego”-<br />

logical biases of modern culture as well as of modern psychology, which<br />

are allegedly complicit with the continuance of environmental problems.<br />

In this light, much of eco-psychology’s subject matter is closely analogous


PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

to that of environmental epistemology, although the latter’s investigations<br />

are, of course, philosophical in character.<br />

Eco-psychologists hold that the citizenry of contemporary modern<br />

society does not contemplate the rhythms and patterns of Nature. They<br />

paint the picture that most persons are so focused on the immediate<br />

tasks of their “daily grind,” that Nature, if anything, is experienced as<br />

an irrelevant backdrop for everyday human dealings and business. Quite<br />

critically, eco-psychologists observe that in contemporary society, the<br />

human individual lives in a human- and self-centered illusory realm,<br />

entirely disconnected from the natural world. All too rarely do they stop<br />

to wonder what this (existence) all is and to think about their relationship<br />

with the natural world. According to eco-psychology, contemporary<br />

modern culture assumes that these questions are not relevant, resulting in<br />

an unreflective mindset that is simply not attuned to the natural world.<br />

In the everyday attitude, the natural, if anything, is considered to be a<br />

mere potentiality, a “stockpile” for fulfilling the instrumental ends of<br />

human beings. With the help of modern technology, the natural world<br />

is developed, appropriated, transformed, prepared, processed, placed into<br />

packaging, and consumed upon demand, all without recognition of the<br />

intrinsic value of “the natural” in this process. Nature is assumed to be<br />

something merely there for human purposes, regardless of the fact that<br />

the average person takes “the natural” for granted within the constitution<br />

of themselves qua “selves.” In the everyday mindset, there is an assumed<br />

metaphysical bifurcation between the self and the natural world, which<br />

is at the root of the ecological crisis. To be sure, eco-psychology suggests<br />

that “the violence we do to ourselves and to the natural world results<br />

from our [posited] psychological and spiritual separation from nature”<br />

(Fisher 21), namely, “a ‘dissociative split’ between spirit and nature . . .<br />

[in which] spirit is not only separated from nature, but incompatible and<br />

opposed [to it]” (Metzner 65). This conceptual bifurcation is assumed<br />

not only in everyday life in contemporary society, 3 but also reinforced by<br />

mainstream psychology.<br />

Eco-psychologists differentiate their discipline from mainstream psychology<br />

in that the latter postulates that the human self is constituted by<br />

an ego which stands statically apart from, and over against, the natural<br />

world. Particularly, they claim that mainstream psychology is reductionistic<br />

in that it focuses on the mental health, the feelings, and the desires<br />

of human beings, both in abstraction from, and to the neglect of any


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

<br />

consideration of the interrelation between the natural world and the mind.<br />

For instance, psychology focuses on alleviating the trials and illnesses of<br />

the human ego, such as depression, fear, grief, and anxiety, by way of<br />

therapy or by way of prescription drugs. Eco-psychologists charge that<br />

in its assumption of the existence of the human ego, and its exclusively<br />

anthropocentric focus on it, mainstream psychology fails to consider the<br />

impact of human thought and action on the natural world. Psychology<br />

presupposes that the natural world and the organic entities helping to<br />

compose it are merely in service to the desires of the human self, there<br />

to be appropriated, consumed, and used up without reference to them<br />

in the constitution of ourselves as “selves.” In traditional psychology, it<br />

is generally presupposed that while healthy persons largely confront the<br />

world and are able to control and appropriate the elements in their surroundings<br />

for themselves, an unhealthy person is one who cannot or does<br />

not, instead experiencing depression, fear, grief, and anxiety, for example,<br />

which need to be treated, as though they were the diseases and not the<br />

symptoms of a greater problem. In this way, eco-psychologists claim that<br />

psychology does not consider that the well-being of the individual egos<br />

experiencing, grasping, and appropriating the natural world are in any<br />

way connected to the health of that world and to the collective health of<br />

the organisms composing it. Conversely, the natural world is not considered<br />

to be a part of the human self, let alone connected with it in any<br />

fundamental way. As such, Kidner states:<br />

within experimental psychology, the separation of the person from the<br />

natural contexts is so complete that no recent theorist has argued for<br />

the necessity of this separation; rather the natural world is considered<br />

to be so far beyond the field of interest of experimental psychology<br />

that this issue is simply not addressed. (“Why” 365)<br />

For Fisher, Kidner, and Roszak, traditional psychology has postulated<br />

and reinforced the existence of a strict metaphysical barrier between the<br />

human ego and the natural world, where, in fact, there is none. Roszak<br />

claims that “psychologists concluded that if [the conception of] the self<br />

were to be expanded so as to include the natural world, then behavior<br />

leading to the destruction of it would be experienced as self-destruction”<br />

(“Nature” 3). And this standpoint would point directly to the necessity<br />

of limiting human appropriation and consumption of the things and<br />

resources of the natural world, namely, of repressing the ego, which would<br />

not only be conceived of as “anti-humanist,” but would be considered


PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

unacceptable, especially in the deeply rooted Freudian tradition of psychology.<br />

Accordingly, for Kidner,<br />

Freud regarded the separation of the self from the external world as<br />

an essential part of both individual development and the progress<br />

of civilization, arguing that the way forward required ‘combining<br />

with the rest of the human community and taking up the attack on<br />

nature, thus forcing it to obey human will, under the guidance of<br />

science.’ (“Why” 366)<br />

“‘Nature,’ Freud dismally concluded, ‘is eternally remote. She destroys<br />

us—coldly, cruelly, relentlessly.’ Whatever else has been revised and<br />

rejected in Freud’s theories, this tragic sense of estrangement from nature<br />

continues to haunt psychology” (Roszak, “Nature” 2). Eco-psychologists<br />

further claim that the bifurcation of ego and natural world, common in<br />

mainstream psychology, is part and parcel of the continued dominance<br />

of Cartesian dualism. Precisely, Descartes postulated an anthropocentric,<br />

mechanistic-materialistic worldview in which reality was composed of<br />

two separate forms of substances: indivisible, thinking substances (res<br />

cogitans) and unthinking, extended, and divisible, material substances (res<br />

extensa), which propagates the conception that the ego is a substance that<br />

is disconnected from the material world. Eco-psychology seeks to heal<br />

the metaphysical split between “inner” and “outer,” as well as between<br />

consciousness and matter, these being the products of “the mature culmination<br />

of Cartesian dualism” (“Why” 367). As summed up by Kidner:<br />

anthropocentric assumptions are intrinsic to the current Western<br />

ideology. While a religious world view necessarily locates humankind<br />

within the context of a greater spiritual scheme, in a mechanistic<br />

world view individuals, by means of rationality, are seen as masters—<br />

or at least potential masters—of a world that is at their disposal. The<br />

conception of a universe in which God is ultimately the controlling<br />

power is replaced by a viewpoint in which technology can enable<br />

humankind to control and utilize the world. (“Why” 366)<br />

In contrast to mainstream psychology, eco-psychology is a holistic<br />

attempt to focus on the complete situation of the human self both within<br />

and compositional of the natural world. Avoiding the reductionism of<br />

the mainstream, it considers mental health from a collective and holistic<br />

perspective, rather than merely from a standpoint that is based on the<br />

assumptions that there exists an individual ego which stands over and<br />

against the world. For instance, eco-psychology considers that the mental<br />

health of one person is dependent upon the mental health of others as


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

<br />

well as the health of the natural environment. Furthermore, as defined<br />

by Fisher, eco-psychology has for its subject matter “neither the human<br />

nor the natural, but the lived experience of interrelationship between the<br />

two” (Radical 31) in a common identity. In other words, eco-psychology<br />

maintains that the diminishment of the human self and the natural world<br />

are reciprocal processes.<br />

On the one hand, eco-psychologists attempt to investigate and locate<br />

reasons for ecological degradation in the most intimate conceptions and<br />

deeply rooted structures of the human psyche and through analysis of<br />

individuals’ understanding of themselves. For them, it is the questionable,<br />

anthropocentric conceptions of the ego, as postulated in traditional<br />

psychology, that create and allow for a lack of reflection leading to the<br />

over-consumption of natural resources. They claim that questionable<br />

conceptions of the ego which are found in psychology contribute to the<br />

excessively instrumental thinking in relation to the natural world that is<br />

dominant in contemporary culture, treating it simply as a means to human<br />

ends. As a result, a central concern of eco-psychologists is to take issue<br />

with “ego”-logical conceptions of the human self. Furthermore, unlike<br />

economic, “reform,” and “management” approaches to environmentalism,<br />

they view “the ecological crisis in existential and spiritual terms, not<br />

merely in technocratic or managerial ones” (Fisher, “Toward” 20).<br />

On the other hand, eco-psychology concerns itself with the psychological<br />

effects of ecological degradation. It focuses on eco-therapy, namely,<br />

the treatment of mental ills occurring as a result of worsening environmental<br />

conditions. For example, eco-psychologists have also detected and<br />

investigated what they call environmental despair and “eco-anxiety,” as<br />

characterized by emotional stress, grief, intense worry, and panic attacks<br />

which are reactions against the increasing alienation of the modern<br />

individual from Nature, as well as rampant environmental destruction.<br />

Roszak and Fisher suggest that “no separation is more pervasive in this<br />

Age of Anxiety than our disconnection from the natural world” (“Nature”<br />

3) and that “any practice that works to release us from the sense of being<br />

a separate, isolated ego set over against the [natural] world, helps to free<br />

us from death anxiety, which some see as a deep source of the human<br />

drive to control and dominate other humans and nature” (“Toward” 25).<br />

Eco-psychologists also investigate “alcoholism, drug abuse, sex addiction,<br />

consumerism, eating disorders, codependence . . .war-making” (Glendinning<br />

54) as well as addictions to technology, rampant in Western society,


PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

which, according to them, are unhealthy ways of coping with the cultural<br />

disassociation of the self from natural world.<br />

Despite providing a more holistic vision for psychology, one critic<br />

of eco-psychology claims that it has, thus far, tended to focus too much<br />

on the human side of the split between self and natural world, and has<br />

not truly “offered a deeper way to understand the psychic-collective<br />

undercurrents of how we came to be at such destructive odds with the<br />

rest of the ecosphere” (Chalquist 21). In this direction, eco-psychology<br />

can only benefit from a dialogue with phenomenology, existentialism,<br />

and process-relational modes of thought in attempting to confront “the<br />

arbitrary and increasingly destructive separation of human consciousness<br />

from its ground and source” (Chalquist 26), namely, the natural world.<br />

As will be shown in the next section of this paper, the general themes<br />

surrounding eco-psychology’s critique of the anthropocentrism of modern<br />

society and of traditional psychology correspond directly with some<br />

important aspects of Jean-Paul Sartre’s view of the self in his existentialist<br />

phenomenology and psychoanalysis. This analysis of Sartre’s philosophy<br />

will also serve to identify the underlying meaning of the anthropocentric<br />

humanism at the root of modernity.<br />

Sartre’s critique of husserl’s “ego”-logical theory and his<br />

articulations concerning the relationship between the<br />

human self and nature<br />

In the mid-twentieth century, the arrival of existentialism shocked the<br />

intellectual establishment in many profound ways. While Sartre’s slogan<br />

that described his own existentialist philosophy was “existentialism is a<br />

humanism,” other figures, like Heidegger and Camus, who were branded<br />

“existentialists,” repudiated the term expressly and distanced themselves<br />

from the notion of humanism. For Sartre, while existentialism was<br />

“humanist,” it was not representative of a naïve humanism. It was nothing<br />

other than the attempt to provide “a coherent atheistic position”<br />

(Existentialism 51). With no given human nature or “self” in the mind of<br />

God to live up to, Sartre’s existentialism consisted in a claim that human<br />

beings are thrown into a world not of their own choosing and that it is the<br />

responsibility of each individual human being, through their choices and<br />

actions, to “nobly” define themselves, and, at the same time, to help define<br />

humanity as a whole. In other words, there is no self but what we make<br />

and there is no essence of humanity prior to its existence. 4 In contrast to


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

<br />

previous humanistic philosophies, Sartre’s existentialism also pointed out<br />

the limits of reason as well as provided a more “authentic” assessment of<br />

the human condition, confronting it head on with anxiety and despair.<br />

Existentialism took many of the initial intellectual steps toward the antihumanism<br />

that is typically associated with the postmodernist thought<br />

that blossomed in the latter half of the twentieth century.<br />

In setting out the main tenets of his existentialist philosophy, Jean-Paul<br />

Sartre examined the underlying meanings behind the conceptual bifurcation<br />

of the human self and the natural world. Sartre was not involved with<br />

environmentalism of any kind. But, although he distinguishes between<br />

empirical psychoanalysis and existentialist psychoanalysis in that while<br />

the former, “aims at reconstituting the life of the subject from birth to<br />

the moment of the cure,” in order to “determine the complex,” and the<br />

latter “seeks to determine the original choice [of being] . . . operating in<br />

the face of the world” (Being 727-28), his phenomenological investigations<br />

lend themselves well to the aims of eco-psychology.<br />

In Nausea, Sartre discusses the existential anxiety and alienation modern<br />

man feels in relation to the natural world, as represented through the<br />

thoughts and feelings of his main character, Roquentin. Roquentin is a<br />

rare individual who contemplates his own existential situation as well as<br />

the place of “the human” in the natural world and he despairs, feeling<br />

that his life is meaninglessness and that existence is absurd. Over the<br />

course of the novel, Roquentin becomes increasingly neurotic and alienated<br />

from the humanistic aims of his vocation as a historian, largely as<br />

a result of his insights into the indifference of the natural world toward<br />

human aspirations and endeavors. In describing Roquentin’s thoughts<br />

and feelings concerning Nature, Sartre writes,<br />

I am afraid of cities. But you mustn’t leave them. If you go too far<br />

you come up against the vegetation belt. Vegetation has crawled<br />

for miles toward the cities. It is waiting. Once the city is dead, the<br />

vegetation will cover it, will climb over the stones, grip them, search<br />

them, make them burst with its long black pincers; it will blind the<br />

holes and let its green paws hang over everything. You must stay in<br />

the cities as long as they are alive, you must never penetrate alone<br />

this great mass of hair waiting at the gates: you must let it undulate<br />

and crack all by itself. In the cities, if you know how to take care of<br />

yourself, and choose the times when all the beasts are sleeping in<br />

their holes and digesting, behind the heaps of organic debris, you


10<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

rarely come across anything more than minerals, the least frightening<br />

of all existents.<br />

I am going back to Bouville. The vegetation has only surrounded<br />

three sides of it. (156)<br />

In this passage, Roquentin’s existential anxiety in relation to the<br />

impending doom of the city at the hands of “the vegetation and the<br />

beasts,” represents a deeply held fear of the destructive powers of Nature.<br />

Nature is here conceived of not only as conditioning human life, but as<br />

determinate of the human condition. Nature is especially understood as<br />

a chaotic entity which is responsible for the temporality of human life<br />

and of human structures, namely, for the transience, finitude, decay, and<br />

perishing of all human life and endeavor.<br />

Since human beings can do nothing to preserve themselves and their<br />

constructions against the ravages of Nature, Roquentin characterizes it<br />

as something to be feared. Roquentin’s anxiety is, in part, the result of<br />

contemplating the threats and challenges that the natural environment<br />

poses to human survival, such as harsh climates, cold, heat, disease, hunger,<br />

thirst, decay, predatory animals, pestilence, floods, droughts, earthquakes,<br />

avalanches, hurricanes, tornadoes, and eruptions of volcanoes, which<br />

human beings attempt to overcome using their reasoning faculties, in order<br />

to preserve the conditions for survival. However, underlying this list of<br />

natural challenges to human beings, Roquetin’s existential anxiety issues<br />

from the recognition that the human condition is comprised by “having<br />

to exist” as a “prisoner” tied into the finitude of his own existence. This<br />

is the meaning of the existentialist notion that human beings are thrown<br />

into a world not of their own choosing, but which is determinate of the<br />

limits and the contours of human experience, life, and existence. One may<br />

speculate that the facts that Nature continuously confronts human beings<br />

with such challenges to its survival, that the natural world determines the<br />

limits and contours of human life, and that the human response is such<br />

that to control and transcend Nature is the only way to attain freedom,<br />

constitute some of the major reasons for why humanity has attempted<br />

to construct both physical and conceptual barriers between the itself and<br />

the natural world. Similarly, these are reasons why the human species has<br />

evolved chiefly through the advance of its technical-rational capacities<br />

which enable it to increasingly control and “master” Nature. To be sure,<br />

throughout its evolution, the human species has been engaged not only in


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

11<br />

a fight for survival against Nature, wherein reason, employed in the “technical-rational<br />

interest” (Habermas 191), is the main “battle weapon.”<br />

In a similar manner to some of the main tenets of eco-psychology’s<br />

investigation of the relationship between the human self and the natural<br />

world, although without a concern for the environment as the chief<br />

impetus, Sartre also took issue with metaphysical conceptions of the<br />

self, which describe it as entirely disconnected from the (natural) world.<br />

In The Transcendence of the Ego (1936), a seminal work from which his<br />

existentialist philosophy was sprung, Sartre provides a critique of Husserl’s<br />

“ego”-logical transcendental idealism that was set out in the latter’s<br />

Cartesian Meditations and elsewhere. While Sartre’s own existentialist<br />

phenomenology is thoroughly indebted to Husserl’s phenomenological<br />

investigations and to its findings, he takes particular issue with Husserl’s<br />

positing of the existence of a transcendental ego at the root of consciousness,<br />

responsible for its unity as the “thing” which thinks.<br />

In The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology,<br />

Husserl outlined some of the connections, as well as the distinctions,<br />

between psychology and phenomenology, which may, for the purposes<br />

of this paper, serve analogously to illuminate the relationship between<br />

eco-psychology and more philosophical modes of investigation. Husserl<br />

claimed that a purely descriptive psychology of consciousness parallels<br />

transcendental phenomenology, in that they may correspond in what they<br />

sought to describe. Husserl thought that psychology was “the truly decisive<br />

field” in bridging the gap between “subjectivism and objectivism” and<br />

that it paralleled phenomenology in that “its subject matter is universal<br />

subjectivity” (Crisis 208). But, he was critically adamant regarding the<br />

distinction between them. Husserl charges that psychology “like every<br />

objective science, is [naïvely] bound to the realm of what is prescientifically<br />

pregiven, i.e., bound to what can be named, asserted, described in<br />

common language” (209), and is fraught with dualistic and physicalistic<br />

assumptions. As such, for him, while psychology operated from “a different<br />

attitude and is under the guidance of a different task” (208) and<br />

holds that data belonging to the world are “presupposed as existing” and<br />

“taken as psychic components of a man,” in phenomenological investigation,<br />

the data “are not taken in this manner, because the whole world,<br />

when one is in the phenomenological attitude, is not accepted as actuality,<br />

but only as an actuality-phenomenon” (Cartesian 32). Husserl further<br />

pointed out that phenomenology avoids the anthropological tendencies


12<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

of empirical psychology. He also sought to reorient psychology toward<br />

the transcendental phenomenological attitude. Interestingly enough, in<br />

a similar manner to eco-psychology’s criticism of mainstream psychology<br />

for not investigating the relationship of the human self and the natural<br />

world, Husserl asked “why has the experience of the bodily thing in the<br />

life-world, as the experience of something ‘merely subjective,’ not previously<br />

been included in the subject matter of psychology?” (Crisis 219).<br />

One of Husserl’s fundamental projects, in relation to his phenomenology,<br />

was to attempt to return to the type of meditation that is found in<br />

Descartes’ philosophy, in order to provide a renewed grounding for the<br />

sciences, while avoiding the latter’s dualistic presuppositions. Parallel<br />

with Descartes’ meditations, Husserl maintained that the findings of<br />

his transcendental phenomenology were universal, and he both clarified<br />

and deepened the meaning of Descartes’ methodic doubt. Consistent<br />

with Descartes’ postulation of the existence of an ego cogito, through his<br />

own transcendental meditations, Husserl “discovered” a transcendental<br />

ego, or “I,” at the core of subjectivity. The transcendental ego was a<br />

main object of investigation for his phenomenology. But, according to<br />

Sartre’s critique, regardless of questions pertaining to phenomenological<br />

methods, the postulation of the existence of a transcendental ego at<br />

the root of consciousness is an unfounded assumption that is left over<br />

from Descartes’ “discovery” of the ego cogito and the resulting bifurcation<br />

of thinking substances (res cogitans) from extended substances (res<br />

extensa). For Husserl, the transcendental ego was universally accessible<br />

to consciousness through the mental procedure of phenomenological<br />

reduction (epochē), or in other words, through the “bracketing-off” of the<br />

“naïve consciousness” of the objective world, and more precisely, of “all<br />

positions taken toward the already-given objective world” (Cartesian 20).<br />

With the employment of phenomenological reduction, which is also a<br />

major point of distinction between his phenomenology and psychology,<br />

Husserl attempted to show that the transcendental ego can be experienced<br />

as a solitary entity, which is responsible for maintaining the unity of consciousness.<br />

It was, for him, the “ego who comes to the fore only with the<br />

transcendental-phenomenological epochē” (25) or this meditative process<br />

of bracketing of the world. Through the phenomenological reduction<br />

to the transcendental ego, Husserl maintained that “the world is for me<br />

absolutely nothing else but the world existing for and accepted by me<br />

in such a conscious cogito” (21). And, for him, in the phenomenological


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

13<br />

attitude “natural being is a realm whose existential status is secondary; it<br />

continually presupposes the realm of transcendental being” (21). While<br />

Husserl himself recognized that his postulation of the transcendental ego<br />

led to the problem of solipsism, and in his fifth meditation, he attempted<br />

to resolve the resulting solipsism through a phenomenological analysis of<br />

the inter-subjectivity of transcendental egos within a common life-world,<br />

Sartre’s critique exploits this lacuna.<br />

Against Husserl’s postulation of the existence of the transcendental ego,<br />

Sartre argues that there is no ego “formally, nor materially in consciousness”<br />

(Transcendence 31) and that “consciousness . . . is never alone, is never<br />

isolated from the existing world” (24). In his criticism, Sartre agrees with<br />

Husserl’s notion of intentionality, a central concept which was first introduced<br />

by Brentano, and which enables the phenomenologist to provide a<br />

description of acts of consciousness. However, Sartre shows how, if taken<br />

to its logical conclusion in phenomenological analysis, it is inconsistent<br />

with the postulation of the existence of a transcendental ego at the root<br />

of consciousness. For Sartre, as for Husserl, the notion of intentionality<br />

means that “all consciousness is consciousness of something” (44), and<br />

suggests that there are two “sides” or “poles” to any intentional act. There<br />

is the “subjective” or the “noetic pole,” which is the “constituting” dimension<br />

of consciousness, and there is the objective or the “noematic pole,”<br />

which encompasses that which is “constituted” in consciousness. Sartre<br />

suggests that there is only intentionality working toward the synthesis that<br />

is consciousness, but there is no pure, essential “I,” or transcendental ego<br />

at its root. He charges that “the “I” of the (Cartesian) “I think” is an object<br />

grasped with neither apodictic nor adequate evidence” (51) and argues, in<br />

a parallel manner, that Descartes’ “I am” presupposes some understanding<br />

of the meaning of being, which he neglected to express or justify.<br />

Instead, Sartre claims that the ego is an illusory construct. He explains<br />

that it may appear to exist, but it is really just reflective consciousness,<br />

namely, it is consciousness intending consciousness and falsely taking it as<br />

an ego. Specifically, the “something” being intended is merely consciousness<br />

being taken as an object by consciousness; it is not a substantial ego.<br />

Furthermore, whereas Husserl argued that the transcendental ego is the<br />

continual “synthesizer” of its past and present experiences, Sartre makes<br />

the case that although “consciousness must be perpetual syntheses of past<br />

and present consciousness . . . it is consciousness which unifies itself, by a<br />

play of transversal intentionalities” (39). As such, for him, the ego is only


14<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

the product of reflective consciousness’ false habit of taking consciousness<br />

as an object, and in turn, taking it as an “I,” a distinct transcendental<br />

subject, namely, a Cartesian substance existing independently from the<br />

world. In this way, Sartre makes the case that the postulation of a transcendental<br />

ego is inconsistent with the notion of intentionality and that<br />

Husserl’s phenomenological analysis is self-contradictory if it is “occupied<br />

with a consciousness shut off or separable from the world” (25). Rather,<br />

for Sartre, if there is a self, then “it is something that exists in the world”<br />

(31), namely, being comprised by a person’s facticity as a phenomenon<br />

for others. And, he writes that this<br />

conception of the ego [as in the world, rather than as transcendent or<br />

separate from it] seems to us the only possible refutation of solipsism.<br />

The refutation that Husserl presents in . . . Cartesian Meditations does<br />

not seem to us capable of unsettling a determined and intelligent<br />

solipsist. As long as the ‘I’ remains a structure of consciousness, it<br />

will always remain possible to oppose consciousness, with its ‘I’, to<br />

all other existents. (103, my addition)<br />

Since the strong counter-claims to Sartre’s criticisms stemming from<br />

a Husserlian transcendental phenomenological stance are not mentioned<br />

here, for example, his aims to “disclose the ‘worldliness’ of consciousness”<br />

(Zaner 387), to elaborate upon phenomenological descriptions of the<br />

embodiment of the human person as well as inter-subjectivity within the<br />

“life-world,” we must conclude that Husserl is certainly not the “straw<br />

man” that Sartre intends in this passage. Nevertheless, in the above passage,<br />

Sartre is alluding to some of the tendencies which are entailed by<br />

“ego”-logical theories. First, “ego”-logical theories may hold that the self<br />

is synonymous with consciousness and the mind, to the exclusion of the<br />

body, as in the Cartesian disconnection between thinking substances<br />

and material substances. Second, they may conceive that the ego is conceived<br />

of as a static, Cartesian thinking substance, defined as that which<br />

is dependent on itself for its own existence. Third, “ego-logical” theories<br />

may presuppose that the self is something that transcends the world,<br />

and/or stands apart and over and against other beings, and not to be a<br />

part of, or compositional of the world. Fourth, they may hold that selfidentity<br />

is to be defined on the basis of identifying what it is not (i.e., the<br />

world or other entities within it), and negating or differentiating itself<br />

from what it is not. 5 Regarding this last ramification, such “negations”<br />

might be interpreted by eco-psychology not only in logical terms, but


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

15<br />

also in environmental ones, precisely, in terms of human beings achieving<br />

some understanding of their own self-identity via the destruction of<br />

the natural world.<br />

While it must be reiterated that Sartre was not involved with environmentalism<br />

during his life, and while elsewhere, in “Existentialism<br />

is a Humanism,” Sartre explains that the Cartesian cogito and human<br />

subjectivity are the “starting point” of existentialism, his critique of “ego”-<br />

logical theories and his situating of the human self as in the world can<br />

be said to serve the aims of eco-psychology. Precisely, it serves to undo<br />

the fallacious notion that human self-identity can be defined by way of<br />

the conception that an ego exists as transcending or as standing over and<br />

against the natural world. Rather, the illusion of a substantial ego existing<br />

within or behind consciousness and transcending the natural world, may<br />

be part and parcel of the total situation of the lived tension of the human<br />

organism in relation to its conditioning by the environment. From an<br />

eco-psychological perspective, if a “self” does indeed exist, it may be said<br />

that it is to be found in the complex interrelationship between the human<br />

organism and the natural world, and not one-sidedly to be associated with<br />

human consciousness or mind. I turn now to an examination of Sartre’s<br />

notion of “the fundamental project of human reality” as descriptive of<br />

the anthropocentric humanism of modernity and an underlying reason<br />

for the human postulation of the existence of a substantial, static ego<br />

standing over and against the natural world.<br />

Sartre’s articulation of “the fundamental project of<br />

human reality” as descriptive of the meaning of the<br />

anthropocentric humanism of modernity<br />

Sartre’s phenomenological analysis of how the ego, conceived of as a<br />

substance entirely separate from the world, is an illusionary construct<br />

closely relates to his conceptualization of what he calls the “fundamental<br />

project of human reality” (Existentialism 63). In Existentialism and Human<br />

Emotions, Sartre writes,<br />

the best way to conceive of the fundamental project of human reality<br />

is to say that man is the being whose project is to be God. Whatever<br />

may be the myths and rites of the religion considered, God is first<br />

‘sensible to the heart’ of man as the one who identifies and defines<br />

him in his ultimate and fundamental project. If man possesses a preontological<br />

comprehension of the being of God, it is not the great<br />

wonders of nature, nor the power of society which have conferred it


16<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

upon him. God, value and supreme end of transcendence, represents<br />

the permanent limit in terms of which man makes known himself<br />

what he is. To be man means to reach toward being God. Or if you<br />

prefer, man fundamentally is the desire to be God. (63)<br />

Sartre’s claim that the fundamental project of human-reality is<br />

the desire to be God can be interpreted as an underlying meaning of<br />

anthropocentric humanism of modernity, or of the human-centered<br />

attitude which many ethicists have pointed to as the chief cause of the<br />

ecological crisis. It must be pointed out that there are many different<br />

religious, cultural, theological, and philosophical conceptions of God,<br />

God’s power, God’s nature, and divine attributes and qualities, such that<br />

one may conclude that Sartre’s notion of the desire to be God is open to<br />

various interpretations. However, if “God” is here defined according to<br />

traditional philosophical definitions, for example as the Prime Mover,<br />

namely, as the ultimate cause of the world, an eminently rational Supreme<br />

Intelligence, an omniscient, self-caused (causa sui) substance, unaffected<br />

by anything else, then Sartre’s notion of the desire to be God is very<br />

much analogous to the assumption that the human self is a Cartesian<br />

substance, namely, an “I,” or ego, conceived as an unconditioned, static<br />

unity, self-caused, entirely self-sufficient, transcendent of the world, not<br />

subject to flux, and dependent only upon itself for its existence. To be<br />

sure, inspired by, and coinciding with his analysis of Hegelian dialectic<br />

and the phenomenological notion of intentionality, Sartre writes, “the<br />

human goal is ‘the in-itself-for-itself’, consciousness become substance,<br />

substance become the cause of itself” (Being 575). By the pursuit of the<br />

“in-itself-for-itself” he means that human individuals, lacking Being and<br />

hence desiring Being, are constantly engaged in the project of escaping<br />

contingency and determining themselves qua “selves,” or their own<br />

facticity as they would have it, ultimately in an attempt to becoming a<br />

self-caused (causa sui) substance, akin to traditional conceptions of God.<br />

And, Sartre claims that “what [ultimately] presides over this project . .<br />

. is the ideal of a consciousness which would be the foundation for its<br />

own being-in-itself by the pure consciousness which it would have of<br />

itself” (723-24, my addition).<br />

In further investigating what he means by the fundamental project<br />

of human reality, in Being and Nothingness, Sartre alludes to the notion<br />

that the “desire to be” is made manifest largely through the activity of<br />

appropriation. 6 <strong>Here</strong>, Sartre’s phenomenological analysis is of interest to


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

17<br />

eco-psychological investigations of desire and consumption. He claims<br />

that desire is comprised of a perceived or conceived “lack of being” and is<br />

“a relation with a contingent and concrete in-itself which it has the project<br />

of appropriating” (Being 725, 747-48). Desire is a drive to possess, to<br />

use, and further, to consume something out of a perceived lack of being,<br />

where “the word ‘consume’ holds the double meaning of an appropriative<br />

destruction and an alimentary enjoyment. To consume is to annihilate and<br />

it is to eat; it is to destroy by incorporating into oneself” (757). As such,<br />

for Sartre, to appropriate something in satisfying desire is, essentially, to<br />

destroy it. He argues that “destruction realizes appropriation” (756-57),<br />

by pointing out that one possesses something by taking over and assuming<br />

sole responsibility for what had, beforehand, existed on its own and was<br />

empirically observable to all. Destroying a thing exemplifies such a taking<br />

over of its being in-itself, negating its being in-itself, and negating the possibility<br />

of its being accessed by others. In appropriating a thing through<br />

destroying it, one “apprehend[s] that ideally I am the foundation of its<br />

being in so far as it is a part of myself and on the other hand to apprehend<br />

that empirically the appropriated object is never valid in itself alone nor<br />

for its [own] individual use” (760, my addition).<br />

According to Sartre, in relation specifically to the desire to be God,<br />

what we really desire to appropriate in an object is the totality of the entities<br />

within the world, so that we can posit ourselves as the foundation of<br />

the world. He writes, “to possess is to wish to possess the world across a<br />

particular object. And, as possession is defined as the effort to apprehend<br />

ourselves as the foundation of a being in so far as it is ourselves ideally”<br />

(Being 762). In expressing this desire, Sartre points to the analogy of<br />

smoking. He states that<br />

to smoke is an appropriative, destructive action. Tobacco is a symbol<br />

of ‘appropriated’ being, since it is destroyed in the rhythm of my<br />

breathing, in a mode of ‘continuous destruction’, since it passes<br />

into me and its change in myself is manifested symbolically by the<br />

transformation of the consumed solid into smoke. . . . The act of<br />

destructively appropriating the tobacco was the symbolic equivalent<br />

of destructively appropriating the entire world. (761)<br />

However, Sartre argues that the desire to be God involves the appropriation<br />

of the totality of entities in the world, in order to posit ourselves<br />

qua selves as the foundation of the world, the project “of being my own<br />

foundation for myself can never be satisfied through [such] appropriation”


18<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

(Being 755), leading to a continuous sequence of desire, conceived of as<br />

a lack of being, which is never satisfied.<br />

While the psychological and phenomenological meanings of the<br />

myriad of human desires, appropriative activities, and actions are, for<br />

Sartre, comprised by the desire to be God, he does not provide a concrete<br />

list of examples which may be said to correspond to this fundamental<br />

project. He states, “while the meaning of the desire is ultimately the<br />

project of being God, the desire is never constituted by this meaning;<br />

on the contrary, it always represents a particular discovery of its ends”<br />

(Being 724). That is to say, Sartre is convinced that “all [human] acts, all<br />

[human] projects translate this choice [of desiring to become God] and<br />

reflect it in a thousand and one ways” (764, my additions), although<br />

they may not exhibit evidence of this desire explicitly, namely, as may be<br />

demonstrated via empirical psychological analysis. The desire to be God<br />

may also be characterized as the human mimicry of God so as to live up<br />

to the Judeo-Christian idea that humanity is made in the image of an<br />

all-powerful God.<br />

From these considerations, however, it may be hypothesized that the<br />

notion of the desire to be God coincides with many of the underlying<br />

human assumptions which are responsible for the environmental crisis.<br />

Particularly, Sartre’s notion of the fundamental project of human-reality as<br />

the desire to be God can be said to offer a grounding, unified description<br />

of humanity’s “manifest destiny” to limitlessly develop and transform the<br />

natural world, to attain economic self-maximization, to engage in excessive<br />

consumerism, to foster ever-increasing levels of economic growth,<br />

to aim at unlimited technological progress, and to master Nature by way<br />

of the instrumental-rational sciences. The notion of the pursuit of the<br />

in-itself-for-itself, as explained by Sartre, is the project to avoid contingency<br />

and to found one’s own Being, and can be said to underlie all of<br />

these endeavors.<br />

Humanity’s endeavor to become dependent only on itself for its<br />

existence, or to liberate itself from the “shackles” of its dependency on,<br />

and determination by the natural world is also part and parcel of the<br />

desire to be God. In this light, Sartre’s notion of the desire to be God<br />

is descriptive of the general sense of the anthropocentric humanism of<br />

modernity. Our arrogant, self-centred ways of thinking in everyday life,<br />

which lead to the systematic appropriation of the natural world, and the<br />

valuation of human goals, interests, inclinations, and preferences as over


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

19<br />

both non-human life and the natural world, is comprised by the desire<br />

to be God. Sartre writes that<br />

man makes himself man in order to be God, and selfness considered<br />

from this point of view can appear to be an egoism; but precisely<br />

because there is no common measure between human reality and the<br />

self-cause which it wants to be, one could just as well say that man<br />

loses himself in order that the self-cause may exist. (Being 796)<br />

That is to say, for Sartre, the “passion” of human beings qua “human”<br />

is to reject, to “nihilate their being,” or to “lose” themselves, attempting<br />

instead to fully transcend the finitude and contingency of their genuine<br />

humanity in order to posit themselves as fully “self-caused,” as in traditional<br />

conceptions of God. In ecological terms, one might speculate<br />

that this rejection involves the rejection of the reality that the natural<br />

world both sustains and supports human life, biologically, mentally, and<br />

spiritually. The desire to be God, rather than being the product of simple<br />

“faith,” may also be interpreted as a psychological attachment to God (or<br />

to the concept of God, conceived of as an infinite substance), in a similar<br />

manner as adolescents being attached to a celebrity, desiring not only to<br />

imitate them, but be them.<br />

For Sartre, however, the constitution of the human self is largely<br />

an existential choice, a desire to determine oneself qua “self” as this or<br />

that. Sartre’s slogan that “existence precedes essence” involves the notion<br />

that we have been thrown into a world not of our own choosing and<br />

that we are radically responsible for who we are and what we become.<br />

The idea that existence precedes essence means that “there is no [given]<br />

human nature” (“Existentialism” 349), namely, there is no such thing<br />

as an essential, or substantial self that is somehow predetermined in the<br />

mind of God. Instead, for Sartre, it is only through the decisions that<br />

we make and the actions that we perform in our lives and experience,<br />

that our Being or essence is determined. It is for this reason that Sartre<br />

emphasizes humanity’s finite freedom in the face of its existential condition,<br />

and it is in this more “sober” sense that he makes the claim that<br />

“existentialism is a humanism.” Therefore, even though Sartre claims that<br />

the best way to conceive of human-reality is as the desire to be God, if<br />

this notion is to remain consistent with the rest of Sartre’s overall critique<br />

of essentialism, then the notion of the desire to be God should not be<br />

considered to provide a definition of the essence of humankind. Rather,<br />

for Sartre, our decisions as individuals in relation to the environment,


20<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

for example, are choices which serve to define “the human” as a whole,<br />

such that the essence of humanity is not fixed in any particular way.<br />

Sartre himself realizes this as he states, “it appears here that the initial<br />

project of being God, which ‘defines’ man, comes close to be the same<br />

as a human ‘nature’ or an ‘essence’” (Being 724). However, the desire to<br />

be God is representative of an existential choice by which human beings<br />

attempt to define themselves chiefly by the mimicry of selected aspects<br />

of God’s nature, powers, attributes, and qualities, and since he labels the<br />

desire to be God here as an “initial choice,” one can speculate that Sartre<br />

himself would want to maintain that human beings are “nothing but<br />

what they make of themselves” (“Existentialism” 349), namely, they are<br />

the entities “by whom values exist” (Being 797) and thus, he would be<br />

open to the widest possibilities for freedom in relation to determinations<br />

of human reality. As will be described in the next sections of this paper,<br />

later in the twentieth century, deconstructive postmodernism provided<br />

an anti-humanist reaction against modern humanity’s desire to be God<br />

and sought to dismantle any conception of an enduring self. In turn,<br />

deconstructive postmodernism opened up a new possibility with which<br />

to define the character of “the human.”<br />

Derrida’s notion of deconstruction<br />

Jacques Derrida’s critique of modernity and of humanistic metaphysics<br />

was more radical than that of the existentialists. As Derrida describes,<br />

within the post-war French intellectual scene, the postmodernist paradigm<br />

that followed from Sartre’s existentialism was constituted by an<br />

“anti-humanist and anti-anthropologistic ebb” (“Ends” 134) that was<br />

largely a reaction against the latter’s left-over humanism and anthropologism.<br />

While, like Sartre, Derrida was not explicitly involved with<br />

environmentalism, a major theme within his critique was the influence<br />

of the use of language in the origination of anthropocentric selfhood.<br />

Advancing beyond Sartre’s critique of “ego”-logical theory, for Derrida,<br />

the postulation of the existence of an ego with similar qualities as traditional<br />

conceptions of God, stems from the metaphysical presuppositions<br />

inherent to language, for example, subject/substance and predicate/accident,<br />

which do violence to the way the world actually is. Derrida charges<br />

that the postulation of the existence of an essential “I” or a substantial,<br />

sovereign ego, conceived as entirely separate from the rest of the world<br />

is, in part, the unfortunate by-product of our reliance on the tool of


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

21<br />

conventional language to represent the world. For Derrida, it is through<br />

the habitual use of language that we start to essentialize the metaphysical<br />

abstractions inherent in it, for example, the Aristotelian assumptions of<br />

subject/substance and predicate/accident, wrongly attributing them to<br />

the way the natural world, and to the things in it, such as the self, actually<br />

are. To be sure, in “Eating Well,” Derrida suggests that “there has<br />

never been The Subject for anyone . . . The subject is a fable . . . but to<br />

concentrate on the elements of speech and conventional fiction that such<br />

a fable presupposes is not to stop taking it seriously” (Peters 313-14).<br />

However, Derrida aims at providing a “critique of consciousness, of the<br />

subject, of self-identity and of self-proximity or self-possession” (314).<br />

As such, while Derrida himself rejected being labeled a “postmodernist,”<br />

as Jean-Françoise Lyotard would define it, namely, by the notion that<br />

“postmodernism is incredulity toward metanarratives” (“Postmodern”<br />

74), Derrida endeavors to employ the notion of deconstruction in order<br />

to subvert the metaphysical assumptions and false essentializations made<br />

through the use of language and employed in human reasoning, especially<br />

the notion of the subject or human self. As one commentator suggests,<br />

deconstructionism is characterized by an anti-humanist “repudiation<br />

of referentiality; the denial of the substantial self and the dissolution of<br />

evaluative discourse, both aesthetic and moral” (Freadmann 115).<br />

In coining the notion of deconstruction, Derrida appropriated<br />

Heidegger’s move to carry out a “Destruktion” (Zerstörung) of the history<br />

of ontology at the beginning of Being and Time, for the purpose<br />

of “loosen[ing] up and dissolv[ing] the concealments” (23) present in<br />

traditional ways of determining the nature of Being, in order to prepare<br />

the way for re-asking the question of the meaning of Being. As Derrida<br />

points out, Heidegger’s destruction was also “directed against humanism”<br />

(“Ends” 34) itself. Derrida fused Heidegger’s concept of Destruktion with<br />

the word, “Abbau,” meaning to “take apart an edifice in order to see how it<br />

is constituted” (Ear 87). With these two notions the term “deconstruction”<br />

was born. As Derrida explains, the intent of deconstruction is to proliferate<br />

diverse interpretations of texts on the basis of “the indeterminacy and<br />

undecideability of meanings” (“Ends” 120), as a result of the absence of<br />

a transcendental signified grounding it.<br />

For Derrida, not only does the human need for meaning-making<br />

through language do violence to the world, but all texts whatsoever, be<br />

they literary, philosophical, or scientific, are left “abandoned,” such that


22<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

interpreters can make whatever they want of them. In other words, for<br />

him, language has no intrinsic, transcendent, authorized, or objective<br />

meaning that needs to be respected. In short, for Derrida, “there is nothing<br />

outside the text” (Grammatology 158), and readers have no duty to<br />

uphold an “intention” by an author, nor any final, univocal, privileged<br />

meaning or transcendental signified behind any text. Rather, all texts are to<br />

be deconstructed, and in fact, for him, all texts are always already deconstructed,<br />

deconstruction being the “active accomplice” (Freadman 117)<br />

of any articulation of meaning, either written or spoken. For Derrida, it<br />

can be demonstrated that any text is, of itself, internally self-reflexive and<br />

contradictory. It is by way of various deconstructive strategies, chief among<br />

them, différance, that Derrida seeks to uncover the inherent contradictions<br />

in any given textual narrative and to prove that it is “complicit . . . with<br />

what [it] denounces[s]” (Norris 48). Différance, meaning simultaneously<br />

to differ and to defer, marks the temporal juxtaposition of meanings in<br />

language, thereby undercutting the notion that a text has a fixed, essential<br />

meaning. For him, there is no discourse or proposition “which has not<br />

already slipped into the form, the logic, and the implicit postulations of<br />

precisely what it seeks to contest” (Wood 286). Even deconstructive texts<br />

may be subject to further deconstruction, resulting in the “whirlpool” by<br />

which language is rendered empty of meaning.<br />

By employing deconstructive techniques, such as différance, Derrida<br />

is not simply interested in discarding truth claims as in ordinary criticism.<br />

Rather, his deconstructive tactics work to undo the notion that<br />

“reason can dispense with [the tool of] language in its quest to arrive at<br />

a pure, self-authenticating truth or method” (Norris 21). Consequently,<br />

deconstruction is focused on the dismantling of reason, Derrida recognizing<br />

that “the scandal of Reason is that nothing seems more natural<br />

than [the] destruction of Nature” (Grammatology 151). For the ultimate<br />

aim of deconstruction is the use of the critical “tools” of philosophy<br />

against reason, and then to throw away those “tools,” leaving behind all<br />

metaphysics and ontology. Without language and reason holding sway,<br />

undoubtedly, human beings would not have a metaphysical, rational, or<br />

conceptual apparatus to cling to, and for that matter, they would not be<br />

able to make arbitrary separations between self and world. In this case, for<br />

Derrida, the possibility of defining “the human” as the animale rationale,<br />

would be brought to an end, thereby unshackling “the human” not only<br />

from the common notion that the rational faculties of human beings


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

23<br />

comprise their essence, but also from metaphysics itself. Corresponding<br />

with this deconstructive enterprise, Derrida quotes from Nietzsche’s Thus<br />

Spake Zarathustra, where the Overman completes the project of active<br />

forgetting, and “without turning back to what he leaves behind him . . .<br />

burns his text and erases the traces of his steps” (“Ends” 152). In the next<br />

section, I will provide an account of Derrida’s employment of deconstruction<br />

against Sartre’s apparent complicity with anthropocentric humanism<br />

in “The Ends of Man,” from which a paradigmatic characterization of<br />

deconstructionism will emerge.<br />

Derrida’s deconstruction of anthropocentric humanism<br />

Derrida’s “The Ends of Man” is a key essay which was heavily influenced<br />

by Heidegger’s Letter on Humanism, in which the latter took issue with<br />

Sartre’s slogan, “existentialism is a humanism.” In it, Derrida attempts todecenter<br />

the notion of a transcendental subject, as well as the anthropocentric<br />

conception that the essence of “the human” is comprised by teleological<br />

purposes through which human projects, endeavors, and practices acquire<br />

their meaning and significance. Particularly, he attacks the common, essentialist<br />

determinations of “the human” as the animale rationale, which, in his<br />

view, perpetuate the notion that any definition of the nature of humankind<br />

must involve a recourse to the “unfolding of teleological reason” (138).<br />

Derrida’s specific focus in the essay, is to deconstruct the humanistic and<br />

“anthropologistic” (132) interpretations of the writings of Hegel, Husserl,<br />

and Heidegger which had held sway over the intellectual scene in postwar<br />

France, doing so on the basis that these philosophers understood their own<br />

projects to be critical of “anthropologism” and “metaphysical humanism”<br />

(122). While Derrida criticizes Hegel, Husserl, and Heidegger for their own<br />

inabilities to overcome humanism, detecting in each of them “a humanism<br />

or an anthropocentrism which necessarily places them, too, among the<br />

last, great metaphysicians” (Zaner 385), he singles out Sartre, especially, as<br />

chiefly responsible for a “mistak[en]” (“Ends” 132) humanistic reading of<br />

the intent of their projects. Specifically, in advancing Heidegger’s critique of<br />

Sartre in the Letter on Humanism, which demonstrated that every humanism<br />

remains metaphysical, Derrida calls into question Sartre’s “humanistic<br />

anthropologism.” He claims that the latter’s slogan “existentialism is a<br />

humanism,” affirming the “nobility” of human life, choices, and action,<br />

as well as his central analysis of the human project of being-in-itself-foritself<br />

comprising the structure of human freedom constituted “nothing


24<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

other than metaphysical unity of man and God, the project of becoming<br />

God as the project constituting human-reality” (“Ends” 131). Derrida<br />

charges that Sartre’s existentialist philosophy, while presenting humanism<br />

in a different, and perhaps more neutral light, did not challenge or overcome<br />

the desire to be God as the fundamental project of human-reality.<br />

Rather, according to Derrida, Sartre’s phenomenological descriptions of<br />

human-reality led him “all too quickly” to proclaim the essence of man,<br />

but also perpetuated and aligned existentialism with this project. To be<br />

sure, Sartre claimed that existentialist psychoanalysis would help to “reveal<br />

to man the real goal of his pursuit, which is being as a synthetic fusion<br />

of the in-itself with the for-itself” (Being 797), and in so doing, pointed<br />

in the direction of becoming self-caused (causa sui) as in the desire to be<br />

God. Therefore, for Derrida, Sartre’s phenomenology and existentialism<br />

are not only descriptively anthropological, but even more strongly, they<br />

are prescriptively anthropocentric.<br />

In challenging the “anthropological” reading of the German philosophers<br />

in postwar France, Derrida points to Sartre’s “monstrous”<br />

translation of Heidegger’s Dasein, namely, that being for whom Being is<br />

an issue for it, as “human-reality.” While he notes that in Sartre’s Nausea,<br />

Roquentin states, “I will not be fool enough to call myself ‘anti-humanist’<br />

. . . I am not a humanist, that’s all there is to it” (“Ends” 153), Derrida<br />

writes that while<br />

certainly [Sartre’s] notion of ‘human-reality’ translated the project of<br />

thinking the meaning of man, the humanity of man, on a new basis,<br />

[but] . . . the unity of man [was] never examined in and of itself. Not<br />

only is existentialism a humanism, but the ground and horizon of<br />

what Sartre calls his ‘phenomenological ontology’ remains the unity<br />

of human-reality. To the extent that it describes the structures of<br />

human-reality, [his] phenomenological ontology is a philosophical<br />

anthropology. (“Ends” 130-31)<br />

In so doing, Derrida claims that by articulating that the fundamental<br />

project of human reality is the desire to be God, Sartre did not follow<br />

through with his own existentialist principle, namely, that existence<br />

precedes essence, and that he unwittingly affirmed a definition of the<br />

essence of humanity. But, Derrida works to deconstruct the essentialization<br />

of “the human” by philosophical anthropologies, including that of<br />

Sartre. He argues that if the desire to be God is indeed the essence of<br />

humanity in our contemporary epoch, then there is a need to overcome


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

25<br />

“the human” and its false metaphysical constructions, in a similar manner<br />

as the proclamation that “man is something to be overcome” (Portable<br />

124) in Nietzsche’s Thus Spake Zarathustra. Lastly, Derrida takes issue<br />

with Sartre’s atheism, charging that regardless of whether or not existentialism<br />

calls itself Christian or atheistic, it remains a metaphysical<br />

humanism. He states that Sartre’s atheism, while seemingly opposed to<br />

metaphysical humanism, “change[s] nothing in the fundamental structure”<br />

(“Ends” 131) of human-reality, conceived in terms of the project<br />

of becoming God. Rather, for Derrida, a deconstruction of the whole<br />

notion of the “sovereign” and “self-caused” subject is required in order<br />

to challenge it.<br />

Conclusively, then, for Derrida, every philosophical determination<br />

of the essence of “the human” chains persons to it and does violence to<br />

human reality. Hence, ultimately, from Derrida’s point of view, freedom<br />

from such determinations requires a complete disbanding of language and<br />

reason. However, in relation to Derrida’s notion of deconstruction and, in<br />

particular, his deconstruction of Sartre’s articulation of the fundamental<br />

project of human reality as the desire to be God, it can be argued that it<br />

opens up a new, competing possibility for defining the character of “the<br />

human.” In that it empties reason, language, metaphysics, ontology, and<br />

the notion of “the human” (notions which have traditionally served to<br />

distinguish man from Nature) of meaning, deconstruction can be characterized<br />

as the mimicry of Nature. Nature is here being characterized<br />

especially in the sense which Sartre elucidates in Nausea, as that which is<br />

responsible for the transience, temporality, finitude, decay, and perishing<br />

of all human structures.<br />

Analogously, deconstruction may be said to be constituted by a<br />

methodic anti-humanist desire to be Nature, dismantling any linguistic,<br />

metaphysical, and ontological barriers erected between humanity and<br />

Nature, be they past, present, or future. From this perspective, deconstruction<br />

is a method of divesting oneself of metaphysics, of “human<br />

selfness,” and of “human projects” in general, namely, of demonstrating<br />

them in their finitude and nullity, metaphorically mimicking the destructive<br />

forces of Nature. In this way, the methodic deconstruction of human<br />

constructions, as in the desire to be Nature, assumes that humanity is on<br />

the way to being Nature, and that the process of assimilating the human<br />

to Nature is one that is still ongoing; deconstruction here being a means<br />

to the end of becoming Nature.


26<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

While Derrida would definitely repudiate the metaphysical presuppositions<br />

that underlie the concept of Nature, as a direct precursor to Derrida,<br />

Nietzsche, in Human, All Too Human, went so far as to say, “we speak of<br />

Nature, and in doing so, forget ourselves: we ourselves are Nature” (Stack<br />

82). Elsewhere, in Homer’s Contest, corresponding to his mantra of “being<br />

faithful to the earth,” Nietzsche similarly stated,<br />

when one speaks of humanity, the idea is fundamental that this is<br />

something which separates and distinguishes man from nature. In<br />

reality, however, there is no such separation: ‘natural’ qualities and<br />

those called truly ‘human’ are inseparably grown together. Man, in<br />

his highest and noblest capacities, is wholly nature, and embodies its<br />

uncanny dual character. (Portable 32, my emphasis)<br />

The difference between Nietzsche and Derrida here seems to consist<br />

in that for the former, there is an assumption that humanity is Nature,<br />

whereas for the latter, the deconstruction of human constructions is in the<br />

“teleological pursuit” of becoming Nature, respectively. The distinction is<br />

between Zarathustra fully “liberated” in the postmodern sense, namely,<br />

completely divested of human constructions and Zarathustra still in the<br />

processes of burning his text and of overcoming humanity. Essentially, it<br />

is a distinction between an “is” and an “ought” or a “desire to be,” where<br />

the basic end seems to be the same, deconstruction being an instrumental<br />

means to that end. In the next section, I will highlight some of the implicit<br />

affinities between radical ecologism and deconstructionism in their joint<br />

critique of anthropocentric humanism.<br />

The anti-humanist affinity between deconstructive<br />

postmodernism and radical ecologism<br />

There is a fundamental illusion in the world that somehow people are<br />

separate from Nature when the reality is that we are a part of Nature,<br />

in fact, we are Nature. And that is probably the most funadamental<br />

misunderstanding that is causing all of this havoc.<br />

~Kenny Ausuabel, Founder of the Bionner Movement. (Eleventh)<br />

Environmental thought in general, including the eco-psychological<br />

movement, has long been criticized and maligned as “anti-humanist”<br />

because of its tendency to put Nature before “the human,” and to limit<br />

human desires, aims, goals, endeavors, such as scientific and technological<br />

progress, development, industrialization, and economic growth in its<br />

attempt to overcome anthropocentrism. It is true that some strands of


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

27<br />

environmentalism ally themselves with deconstructionism in order to<br />

accomplish these tasks. For instance, in describing some of the commonalities<br />

and affinities between deconstructionism and environmentalism in<br />

respect to the critique of anthropocentric humanism, Arne Naess agreed<br />

with Michael Zimmerman to the effect that “deep ecologists agree with<br />

Derrida’s deconstruction of anthropocentrism, however, they resist [any]<br />

deconstruction of nature, wilderness and ecosphere” (“Heidegger” 1). For<br />

them, the deconstruction of human constructions would seem to be an<br />

ongoing method for ecological thought to close the gap between humanity<br />

and Nature, eliminating their metaphysical separation. Especially, as John<br />

Seed points out, for ecologism, “‘anthropocentrism’ or ‘homocentrism’<br />

means human chauvinism [or egotism] . . . the idea that humans are the<br />

crown of creation, the source of all value, the measure of all things [notions<br />

which are] deeply embedded in our culture and consciousness” (Devall,<br />

et al. 243, my additions). And, in so far as deconstruction deconstructs<br />

anthropocentric discourses, it is a “useful tool” of radical ecologism. In<br />

this way, deconstruction and radical ecologism are joined “at the hip.”<br />

Deconstruction, as the desire to be Nature, is a tool which radical<br />

ecologism employs in defending the notion that human beings are on<br />

the way to return to Nature or to a “non-modern” and/or a non-technological<br />

way of life, which are more aligned with “the natural.” While<br />

it may be charged that human beings never “left Nature in the first<br />

place” nor could they ever do so, radical ecologism entails a systematic<br />

deconstruction of all human structures and developments which are<br />

deemed to be “modern,” such as scientific and technological progress,<br />

the meta-narratives of modernity, as well as all philosophical reflection. 7<br />

Furthermore, in deconstruction, as the desire to be Nature, humanity is<br />

something to be overcome. It means that a person is a libidinal animal.<br />

In relation to the latter possibility, Derrida criticizes the residues of<br />

humanism in Heidegger’s Letter on Humanism, where the latter insists<br />

on maintaining the dignity of man through a distinction between<br />

human and animal. And, playing on the Cartesian proposition, ego<br />

cogito ergo sum, in his later essay, “The Animal That Therefore I Am,”<br />

Derrida refuses to recognize any human independence from animality,<br />

and flirts with deconstructing the distinction between the human self<br />

and the wild animal. The project to situate “the human” in “the wild<br />

animal” is also a common vein in radical anti-humanist ecologism, in<br />

part constituting the meaning of its anti-humanism.


28<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

Deconstructionism and radical ecologism also couple themselves<br />

in that the notion that humanity is Nature ties in with Deep Ecology’s<br />

principles for intervening in, and counteracting, anthropocentric activities,<br />

such as slash-and-burning a rainforest so as to develop the land.<br />

Deep Ecologists employ the term “ecological resisting” in which one,<br />

for example, does what is necessary to protect the ecosystem. Ecological<br />

resisting implies that in protecting the rainforest, one is protecting oneself.<br />

There is an implicit identification of oneself with Nature, namely, an<br />

erasure of the metaphysical separation between Nature and the human. As<br />

Seed suggests, the idea that “I am protecting the rainforest . . . develops<br />

into ‘I am part of the rainforest protecting myself’” (Devall et al. 199).<br />

He continues, “what a relief then! The thousands of years of imagined<br />

separation are over and we begin to recall our true nature . . . the change<br />

is a spiritual one” (243). Certainly, an identification of oneself as a part<br />

of Nature is a positive step in defending the environment. However, it<br />

is a fallacious and dangerous idea to identify oneself with the collective<br />

totality of all organisms composing Nature, as though one’s own interests<br />

are completely at one with the single living and self-regulating system that<br />

is Nature. To think that one speaks for, or acts on behalf of the totality of<br />

the organisms which also help to compose Nature, or to want to do so,<br />

is the height of dogmatism.<br />

While Deep Ecologists emphasize non-violence in ecological resisting,<br />

it is easy to see how the principle of ecological resistance can be taken to<br />

a radical extreme, implying violence. For example, Derrida’s deconstruction,<br />

interpreted as the desire to be Nature, can be said to accompany<br />

the strict anti-humanism and biocentrism of a radical ecological standpoint.<br />

In light of the ecological crisis, some strands of radical ecologism<br />

postulate the very existence of human beings qua “human” as the central<br />

“problem” and therefore we ought to fully erase the human and become<br />

one with the destructive powers of Nature. As made infamous by the<br />

Earth Liberation Front (E.L.F.), some streams of radically anti-humanist<br />

ecologism attempt to mimic the destructive powers of Nature, as against<br />

human structures, engaging in acts of vandalism, arson, and terrorism.<br />

For example, the E.L.F. has allegedly spiked trees in order to prevent<br />

logging, sabotaged biotechnology industry buildings, and set fire to<br />

hotel and ski resort structures (Pierce 77-81). Radical anti-humanist<br />

ecologism would perhaps applaud the devastation that occurred in New<br />

Orleans as a result of Hurricane Katrina, holding that it serves the human


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

29<br />

species right for their ecologically destructive activities. Ironically, one<br />

is reminded here of the claims of some New Orleans citizens that Hurricane<br />

Katrina was God’s punishment for their sinful way of life. Also,<br />

for example, radical anti-humanist ecologism may treat human life as<br />

“parasitical” on the natural world.<br />

In Earth in the Balance, Al Gore claims that radical ecological views<br />

essentially commit a “deep mistake of defining our relationship to the earth<br />

using the metaphor of disease” (216-17), precisely that the human species<br />

is an “evil,” unnatural alien species; an invading virus or plague that is<br />

parasitical on the health and equilibrium of an otherwise pristine, unique,<br />

noble, and integral planet, thereby perpetuating a new metaphysical split<br />

between “the human” and “the natural.” Radical ecologism’s anti-humanism<br />

may be characterized by an over-emphasis on the Nature-side of the<br />

human-Nature relationship, and a denigration of “the human.” But, by<br />

doing so, the biocentric mimicry of Nature via deconstruction and/or on<br />

the part of radical ecologism fails to recognize the generative and “creative”<br />

aspects of Nature. Instead, they emphasize its destructive side in relation<br />

to human beings and their endeavors.<br />

While it is the case that human beings are a part of Nature, it does not<br />

follow that human beings are Nature or could ever be Nature. Human<br />

beings exist entirely within Nature, help to compose it, and are dependent<br />

on it. They partake of, or have “natural” or “wild” aspects within themselves,<br />

ideas which most environmentally-oriented modes of thought,<br />

including eco-psychology, seek to promote. From this perspective, there<br />

is no strict ontological division that could be erected between man and<br />

the rest of the natural world. At the same time, this does not necessarily<br />

mean that humanity is Nature.<br />

In general, environmental thought, in general, tends to emphasize that<br />

human beings do not exist in a vacuum and that they are a part of Nature.<br />

Human beings are organisms who are physically, mentally, and spiritually<br />

dependent on Nature. Biologically, without the oxygen from plants<br />

and trees, water from lakes and rivers, and food from plants and animals,<br />

human beings cannot survive. Similarly, what we call “our” breath is the<br />

air around us that is inhaled, appropriated into our lungs and exhaled, or<br />

pumped out; it is not explicitly “ours.” The human body does not create<br />

the air that is “our” breath, nor does it contribute to creating the oxygen<br />

that the organism needs to survive. Mentally, human beings cannot<br />

survive in a vacuum, without the stimuli from the natural environment


30<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

on the planet Earth. One can imagine that even the fittest cosmonauts<br />

traveling out in the empty nothingness of space for extended periods of<br />

time would experience feelings of existential anxiety and possible mental<br />

break-down. 8 It may be concluded, therefore, that Nature provides objective<br />

and aesthetic experience necessary for mental health. Our emotional,<br />

mental, and spiritual well-being is dependent on feeling the diversity of<br />

organisms and the surroundings provided by life on Earth. In consideration<br />

of our spiritual dependence on Nature, the etymological meaning of the<br />

word “Spirit” (Latin spiritus), is “breath.” As mentioned previously, what<br />

we call “our breath” is the air around us, namely, the product of the biosphere<br />

that is inhaled; it is not explicitly “ours.” This fact points viscerally<br />

to the connection between the human creature and Nature. Analogously,<br />

the content of Spirit is only what the human organism has experienced in<br />

the past, “inhaled” so to speak, or appropriated from the natural world,<br />

and “exhaled,” such that the meaning of the notion that human beings<br />

are Nature may reside in the notion that the Being of any human being is<br />

comprised by “the natural.” Similarly, “the natural” is not explicitly “ours.”<br />

In particular, the objects, organisms, events, and creatures that we experience<br />

are selectively appropriated and provide for the symbolic content<br />

of what we conventionally call “Spirit.” It is impossible to imagine any<br />

content that is not derived either explicitly from, or is a composite of the<br />

entities and occasions of the natural world. It is along these lines that the<br />

human self can be situated among the entities of the natural world, rather<br />

than completely transcendent of them, an observation coinciding with<br />

the findings of eco-psychology, and also somewhat similar to a Humean<br />

empiricist stance on the origins of “the spiritual.” Because human beings are<br />

dependent on the rest of the natural world in these many ways, to use earth,<br />

air, and sky essentially as “open sewers,” as we do, is to do severe damage to<br />

ourselves. Certainly, if the environmental crisis is to be addressed seriously,<br />

one of the most important notions to realize is that the human self, from<br />

its biological, mental, and spiritual dimensions, is a part of Nature, rather<br />

than opposed to it. However, logically speaking, to reduce Nature to being<br />

a predicate/accident of the subject/substance, “human beings,” as in the<br />

proposition, “human beings are Nature,” or to affirm a one-to-one correspondence<br />

between them, does real violence to both entities. Furthermore,<br />

human beings cannot legitimately presume to think themselves and their<br />

own interests are simply synonymous with the totality of organisms which<br />

help to compose Nature, as if to assume that they are it.


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

31<br />

What has been intimated through the preceding analysis is that a<br />

dialectic has emerged regarding the ultimate ends and essence of “the<br />

human,” which is descriptive of the current “crossroads” surrounding<br />

environmentalism. Particularly, this dialectic concerns the eco-psychological<br />

investigation of the assumed separation of the human self from<br />

the natural world, as well as issues of sustainability and development. I<br />

have highlighted the tension between the desire to be God which may<br />

be associated with the goals of modernism and its overall worldview, and<br />

the desire to be Nature, which may be associated with the ultimate ends<br />

of deconstructive postmodernism and radical ecologism. Certainly, in<br />

light of the environmental crisis, constituted by modern man’s desire for<br />

unlimited development, economic growth, and for technological mastery<br />

over the Earth, the anthropocentric desire to be God must be curtailed.<br />

And deconstruction may offer a means to detach oneself from God or<br />

from the concept of God. However, while a great deal of movement<br />

must be made in the direction of the criticism of the anthropocentric<br />

humanism of modernity, we ought not to revert to the opposite position<br />

of radical deconstructionism. There is need to recognize “the human” as a<br />

part of Nature, to situate the “human self” amidst the natural world, and<br />

to recognize “the natural” within the human self. However, deconstructive<br />

postmodernism’s and radical ecologism’s anti-humanist desire to be<br />

Nature, constituted by a methodic emptying of metaphysics, language,<br />

and reason, as well as any conception of an enduring self, which arguably<br />

have allowed the human species to survive, must also be curtailed. Both<br />

the desire to be God and the desire to be Nature, taken to their ultimate<br />

conclusions, lead inevitably to the extinction not only of the human species,<br />

but also of the majority of other life-forms and species on the planet.<br />

While one consists in the complete outstripping of the Earth’s life-support<br />

system through over-development, over-consumption, and the will<br />

to technological mastery, the other consists in the project to dismantle<br />

humanity’s rational capacities which have secured its survival. However,<br />

in overcoming these competing drives, it may be claimed that human<br />

beings contain what one may call “divine” and “natural” aspects within<br />

themselves, each distinct yet thoroughly interpenetrating, where neither<br />

can be said one-sidedly to offer a genuine definition of their essence. To<br />

be sure, near the end of his life, Sartre, even after emphasizing the nullity<br />

and absurdity of human existence throughout his life, when questioned by<br />

Simone de Beauvoir about the staunch atheism he had held throughout


32<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

his life, admitted that “even if one does not believe in God, there are elements<br />

of the idea of God that remain in us and that cause us to see the<br />

world with some divine aspects” (de Beauvoir 436-43). In this light, in<br />

the last section of this paper, I will endeavor to express how the processrelational<br />

standpoint overcomes the anthropocentrism of modernism and<br />

the extreme anti-humanism of deconstructive postmodernism and radical<br />

ecologism, as characterized above.<br />

<strong>Overcoming</strong> the dichotomy between anthropocentric<br />

humanism and radical anti-humanism via the “critical,<br />

non-anthropocentric organicism” of “process-relational”<br />

environmental epistemology<br />

In the “Introduction to the SUNY Series in Constructive Postmodern<br />

Thought,” David Ray Griffin contrasts what he calls “constructive” or<br />

“reconstructive” postmodernism, of which process-relational modes of<br />

thought are the chief example, with “deconstructive” or “eliminative”<br />

postmodernism. He claims that the latter<br />

overcomes the modern worldview through an anti-worldview,<br />

deconstructing or even entirely eliminating various concepts that<br />

have generally been thought necessary for a worldview, such as self,<br />

purpose, meaning, a real world, givenness, reason, truth as correspondence,<br />

universally valid norms, and divinity. . . . [However] the<br />

postmodernism [derived from process-relational modes of thought]<br />

can, by contrast, be called revisionary, constructive, or—perhaps<br />

best—reconstructive. It seeks to overcome the modern worldview<br />

not by eliminating the possibility of worldviews (or metanarratives)<br />

as such, but by constructing a postmodern worldview through a<br />

revision of modern premises and traditional concepts. . . . That is,<br />

it agrees with deconstructive postmodernists that a massive deconstruction<br />

of many received concepts is needed. But its deconstructive<br />

moment, carried out for the sake of the presuppositions of practice,<br />

does not result in self-referential inconsistency. It also is not so totalizing<br />

as to prevent reconstruction. . . . Going beyond the modern<br />

world will involve transcending its individualism, anthropocentrism,<br />

patriarchy, economism, consumerism, nationalism, and militarism.<br />

(xii-xiii, my additions)<br />

As a “constructive” or “reconstructive” form of postmodernism, the<br />

process-relational standpoint that is inspired by the philosophy of Alfred<br />

North Whitehead deviates from the postmodernism of the “deconstructionist”<br />

variety. It is highly critical of the anthropocentric humanism that


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

33<br />

is characteristic of modernity, the pretense to unlimited development, and<br />

the domination of the global marketplace and instrumental reason, yet,<br />

at the same time, it does not aim to provide a totalizing deconstruction<br />

of all that might be associated with “modernity” or with “the human.”<br />

Whitehead notes that one of the main differences between the human<br />

beings who lived in previous societies and those living in modern societies<br />

is that in the former “nature controlled them, while we now see our<br />

way to the control of nature” (ESP 25). And, recognizing the precarious<br />

ecological situation humanity finds itself in today, in its overemphasis<br />

on controlling Nature, Griffin asserts that constructive postmodernism<br />

is “based on the awareness that the continuation of modernity threatens the<br />

very survival of life on our planet” (Allan ix). However, process-relational<br />

thought, exemplifying the meaning of “constructive” postmodernism,<br />

neither gives in to despair, nor does it accept the jettisoning of reason by<br />

way of deconstructive postmodernism in favor of undecideability. Rather,<br />

in response to the ecological crisis, it remains critically committed to generating<br />

and exploring creative alternatives for human thought and action,<br />

rather than pursuing an anti-humanist course of relentless deconstruction<br />

which is not accompanied by any positive proposals for reconstruction.<br />

While exceptionally critical of the pretense to unlimited technological<br />

progress, of instrumental reason, and of the modernist assumption that<br />

the solution to the problem of climate change is to be found solely in the<br />

development of a “technological fix,” the process-relational perspective<br />

does not, for example, rule out innovations toward “green” technologies,<br />

such as wind and solar power.<br />

Whitehead’s epistemology and cosmology provides a description of<br />

how human beings are intrinsically connected with the natural world. He<br />

states that the “first principle of epistemology should be that the changeable,<br />

shifting aspects of our relations to nature are the primary topics for<br />

conscious observation” (MT 29). Epistemology, for him, should include<br />

an examination of “our whole experience [as] composed out of our relationships<br />

to the rest of things [including ‘intimate vague experiences’,<br />

not just of distinct sense-data], and of the formation of new relationships<br />

constitutive of things to come” (MT 31, my additions). Hence, in<br />

Whitehead’s epistemology, there is a consideration of the widest variety<br />

of occasions of experience, not just those of the conscious variety which<br />

most other philosophers privilege in their investigations. For him, the more<br />

obscure and “lower-level” forms of experience (e.g., physical feelings) tell


34<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

us more about our condition as organisms and our connection to Nature<br />

than “high-level” conscious experience. In fact, Whitehead holds that the<br />

former are the basis for the latter.<br />

Whitehead defines Nature as a felt “complex of related entities<br />

[wherein] the ‘complex’ is fact as an entity for thought, to whose bare<br />

individuality is ascribed the property of embracing in its complexity the<br />

natural entities” (CN 13). From this perspective, the notion that human<br />

beings are a part of Nature means that they are one type of entity among<br />

“the many” natural entities which in their interconnection compose “the<br />

one” relational complex that is Nature. While human beings are a part of<br />

Nature, they are not themselves identical to the total complex of entities<br />

that is Nature. Whitehead’s cosmology is based in the notion that the<br />

natural “world is not made up of independent things, each determinate<br />

in abstraction from all the rest” (ESP 157). Rather, Nature is comprised<br />

by an extensive continuum which is conceptually “divisible, but not in<br />

fact divided” (PR 62). From a Whiteheadian perspective, the Cartesian<br />

postulation that the world is composed of thinking and material substances,<br />

dependent only upon themselves for their existence and entirely<br />

separate from the natural world, is a fallacious abstraction based on such<br />

a conceptual division. For Whitehead, Nature is an “organic extensive<br />

community” (PR 289) which is thoroughly in process and composed of<br />

living organisms, or what he calls “actual entities” or “actual occasions.”<br />

Actual entities are finite “creatures which become” (PR 35), each of which<br />

is engaged in its own creative life-process, and each partly constituted<br />

by its various relations with other actual entities. A person, at a given<br />

moment, is but one example of an actual entity and, as such, a person,<br />

as helping to compose Nature, is not a site where Nature may be said to<br />

“end.” According to Whitehead, “the demarcation [of the human body]<br />

from the rest of nature is vague in the extreme . . . There is no definite<br />

boundary to determine where the body begins and external nature ends”<br />

(MT 161). But, as a finite, yet enduring part of the relational complex of<br />

entities that is Nature (at least in the context of the present evolutionary<br />

epoch), “the human” cannot be said to have its identity in terms of the<br />

totality of Nature.<br />

In relation to its environmental epistemological standpoint, processrelational<br />

modes of thought overcome the vicious dichotomy between the<br />

anthropocentric humanism of modernity, which is exemplified by the Sartrean<br />

articulation that human reality is constituted by the desire to be God,


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

35<br />

and the extreme anti-humanism of deconstructive postmodernism and<br />

radical ecologism, which have been characterized in this paper as advancing<br />

the desire to be Nature by attempting to divorce humans from “the<br />

human,” that is, all past, present, and future modes of human being and<br />

experience as well as all determinations of the nature of “the human.” The<br />

process-relational stance may be termed a “critical, non-anthropocentric<br />

organicism,” pointing to the contrast between the extremes of the desire<br />

to be God and the desire to be Nature in relation to the ultimate ends<br />

of humanity, rejecting both of these extremes. From a process-relational<br />

perspective, human beings qua “human” are neither God, nor Nature;<br />

neither everything, nor nothing, in their “purified” senses, nor could they<br />

presume to be. Rather, process-relational modes of thought hold that<br />

human beings are finite parts of Nature, helping to compose its complex<br />

relationality, yet possessing “spiritual” qualities within themselves as well,<br />

Nature and mind being inseparably intertwined together.<br />

The process-relational standpoint, in part, agrees with Sartre’s existentialism<br />

in the sense that organisms determine their own character by<br />

way of the facticity of their own lives and experience, i.e. through their<br />

creative life-processes and the “objective immortality” of their pasts.<br />

However, process-relational philosophy adds that in the lives of organisms,<br />

the objectively immortal past also helps to determine the content<br />

and course at which subsequent creativity aims, and that determinations<br />

of the character of an organism must take into account the fact that the<br />

entity in question is partly, yet not wholly, constituted by its various<br />

relations to other entities. As such, going deeper than existentialism’s<br />

notion that “existence precedes essence,” the process-relational perspective<br />

asserts that neither existence nor essence can be said to “be prior<br />

to” the other, thus postulating that the enduring character of organisms,<br />

including that of human beings, is in the process of being determined<br />

through their lives and experience, even if momentary experience is<br />

perpetually perishing through time. In this sense, in its emphasis on flux<br />

and “process,” the Whiteheadian perspective agrees with the existentialist<br />

emphasis that temporality and finitude are what “finalize” the natures<br />

of entities. Furthermore, from a process-relational perspective, answers<br />

to the question of what the nature of humanity is, are to be considered<br />

speculative approximations and descriptions of an “enduring character,”<br />

rather than an essence or a necessary pre-given nature, which is dependent<br />

on the evolutionary epoch within which it arises as well as its concrete


36<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

relations to other entities. Whitehead’s notion of an “enduring character”<br />

is meant to supplant the misplaced concreteness of determinations of the<br />

“essence” or the “nature” of things, or of humanity for instance. Against<br />

such essentialist tendencies, from the process-relational perspective,<br />

the enduring character of humanity is continually in flux, and without<br />

“privileged moments,” wherein any determination of it is never fixed and<br />

final, but rather open to revision, corresponding with the notion that<br />

human beings, like all other actual entities, are not static substances.<br />

However, in contrast to deconstructive postmodernism, with its massive<br />

critical attack on essentialism, from the process-relational standpoint,<br />

we can still entertain such discussions regarding the “enduring character<br />

of ‘the human’.”<br />

To a certain extent, Whitehead shares in the postmodernist criticism<br />

of language. He states that it is “hopelessly ambiguous” and inadequate<br />

to express actuality and he criticizes “the habit of thinking of words<br />

as fixed things with specific meanings . . . [because in actuality] the<br />

meanings of language are in violent fluctuation” (Dialogues 296-97).<br />

Whitehead further suggests that the abstractions of linguistic expression<br />

“lead . . . away from the realities of the immediate world” (MT 39). But,<br />

Whitehead does not take the deconstructionist turn. From the process<br />

philosophical stance, all characterizations of the enduring character of<br />

“the human” are to be interpreted as speculative approximations from<br />

within the confines of conventional language. In recognizing these limitations,<br />

philosophy may continue to express “the character of the human,”<br />

without the essentializations and/or the misplaced concretenesses which<br />

do violence to its actuality.<br />

If one insists on having “a determination of the nature of the human”<br />

from the process-relational standpoint, then it can be affirmed that,<br />

according to Whitehead, the enduring character of the human in our<br />

contemporary epoch involves recourse to the notion of creativity. Human<br />

beings are creative organisms, creativity, for Whitehead, being their “grandeur”<br />

and “dignity” (Dialogues 371). For him, human beings are finite<br />

“co-creators” in conjunction with God, Nature, and all other organisms<br />

in the natural world. In Whitehead’s cosmology, the notion of creativity<br />

is a holistic expression of the totality of organic experience, where each<br />

organism engages in its own particular creative processes and is constituted<br />

by it. Consequently, a determination of the character of “the human”<br />

from the aspect of creativity entails a focus on the human organism in


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

37<br />

its full complexity, including its concrete experience, its faculties, its aims<br />

and purposes, its feelings and emotions, its strengths, its weaknesses, its<br />

suffering, its finitude, its lived connections with the other actual entities<br />

which help to compose Nature, and so on— and not merely, for instance,<br />

by way of their “rational faculties.” In response to the imminent criticism<br />

that in suggesting that creativity pervades Nature, Whitehead is anthropocentrically<br />

ascribing human creativity and human qualities to other<br />

organisms, it should be pointed out that for him, “the human” has itself<br />

emerged both within and from Nature, and not vice-versa.<br />

One striking feature of Whitehead’s cosmology of organic interdependence<br />

is that in contrast to traditional Christian conceptions of God, God<br />

is neither conceived to be an asymmetrical causal force on the natural<br />

world, nor transcendentally apart from it. In <strong>Process</strong> and Reality, Whitehead<br />

provides a profound critique of the combination of both “the notion<br />

of God [interpreted] as the ‘unmoved mover’ [as] derived from Aristotle . .<br />

. [and] the notion of God as ‘eminently real’ [which] is a favorite doctrine<br />

of Christian theology,” which have been fused by Western culture into the<br />

idea of “an aboriginal, eminently real, transcendent creator, at whose fiat<br />

the world came into being, and whose imposed will it obeys” (PR 342).<br />

Unlike many traditional understandings of God’s qualities which dwell<br />

on the notion of God as a Prime Mover, or as an infinite, transcendent,<br />

or self-caused substance, an Almighty causal force from and by which<br />

the temporal world is generated and kept in motion, which have served<br />

to bifurcate God and the natural world, Whitehead’s own cosmology<br />

holds that God has a “finite or temporal side,” which is immanent in the<br />

world and not statically outside of it. For Whitehead, God is not to be<br />

conceived as a condescending Caesar, radically separated from and unaffected<br />

by the world, yet somehow directing the unfolding of all creatures.<br />

Thus, by providing an alternative conception of God which is not based<br />

in Cartesian substance ontology, and one which is far removed, as Jones<br />

writes in her introduction to Religion in the Making, from “a notion of<br />

divine immutable essence and eternal normative will” (xxxiii), Whitehead’s<br />

cosmological rubric does not lend itself to human mimicry of God,<br />

conceived as an infinite, self-caused substance, which, as has been characterized<br />

in this paper, is the underlying root of the anthropocentricism<br />

which is responsible for the environmental crisis. In this way, Whitehead’s<br />

critique of traditional understandings of the definition and the qualities<br />

of God and his own cosmological formulations regarding the character


38<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

of God provide a “psychological inoculation” against the human desire<br />

to be God which is at the root of the ecological crisis.<br />

Whitehead’s cosmology presents to us the novel alternative of “panentheism,”<br />

meaning, as Griffin explains, that “the [natural] world is present<br />

in deity and deity is present in the [natural] world” (Spirituality 17, my<br />

addition), God and Nature being interconnected and intermingling poles<br />

of the creative process. In his scheme, God is with the natural world<br />

and is in turn receptively affected by it. In his perspective, God and the<br />

natural world are partners which are caught “in the grip of the ultimate<br />

metaphysical ground, the creative advance into novelty” (PR 349), each<br />

standing together in their mutual requirement. It is not that God and<br />

the natural world are two distinct aspects of identical substance, as in<br />

pantheistic standpoints such as that of Spinoza. Rather, for Whitehead,<br />

God and Nature are equal, reciprocal, symmetrical, contrasting, and codependent<br />

poles of the creative process, which is the ultimate foundation<br />

for the cosmological order of things. As such, for him, neither God nor<br />

the World can be conceived of as static substance entirely separate from<br />

the other. According to him, “in every respect God and the World move<br />

conversely to each other in respect to their process” (PR 349); 9 the traditional<br />

bifurcation of God and the World being bridged via the principle<br />

of creativity. In his cosmological scheme, both God and the World can<br />

be considered “interlocking poles” within the creative process, where the<br />

natural world is not considered merely as that which is responsible for the<br />

temporality, flux, finitude, destruction, and perishing of human creative<br />

endeavor, and as somehow “evil.” Rather, for Whitehead, temporality, flux,<br />

finitude, destruction, and perishing also belong to the Being of God. For<br />

him, perishing is in some ways a generating force in the creative process,<br />

which may not only finalize that particular process of self-creation, rendering<br />

it objectively immortal, or an unalterable stubborn fact belonging<br />

to the past, but also may be considered a moment in the fluency and/or<br />

refreshment of its creative life-process.<br />

As part of his speculative cosmology, Whitehead embraces pan-experientialism.<br />

For him, subjectivity and feeling pervade the natural world,<br />

and whether or not the entities in question are considered either animate<br />

or inanimate, they participate in the overall creative advance of the<br />

universe. For Whitehead, creativity is “universal throughout actuality”<br />

(PR 164), namely, all temporal creatures participate interdependently in<br />

the creative evolution of the universe, and they have importance to the


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

39<br />

whole cosmological scheme of things. He states that while “no entity<br />

can be considered in abstraction from the universe . . . no entity can<br />

be divested of its own [distinct] individuality” (MG 678, my addition),<br />

again pointing to the notion that human beings (and their interests)<br />

cannot be regarded as synonymous with (those of) the total complex of<br />

organisms that, together, compose Nature. Whitehead further suggests<br />

that while “no entity can be divorced from the notion of creativity,”<br />

each infuses “its own particularity into creativity” (PR 213). Elsewhere,<br />

he states that the creative principle is everywhere in Nature, namely, “in<br />

animate and so-called inanimate matter, in the ether, water, earth, [and<br />

in the] human” (Dialogues 370). As such, the statement that the notion<br />

of creativity provides an adequate description of the enduring character of<br />

humanity is not representative of a definition of “the human” which has<br />

its basis in a logical opposition to all other actual entities, for example,<br />

plants, animals, God, or Nature. That said, human creativity could be<br />

said to involve specific accidental qualities, characteristics, operations, and<br />

activities, such as “reasoning faculties,” consciousness, self-consciousness,<br />

language, negation, skepticism, criticism, valuation, selectivity, faith,<br />

teleology, and so on, which makes it distinct (in terms of degree) from<br />

other actual entities. But, each of these qualities, characteristics, operations,<br />

and activities can neither be interpreted in abstraction from other<br />

such characteristics so as to define the essence of “man,” nor do they make<br />

human creativity superior to the creativity of other actual entities. Hence,<br />

Whitehead’s stance is more accurately to be described as an “organicism,”<br />

rather than as a “humanism,” and it is especially critical of the anthropocentric<br />

humanisms of the modernist variety. Unlike anthropocentric<br />

humanisms which neglect the fact that a human being is an object for<br />

the creativity of others and for other organisms, for Whitehead, both a<br />

human being’s physical pole (i.e. body) and its mental pole (i.e. mind)<br />

are “objective data,” much like other entities are for it. For instance, a dog<br />

feels, recognizes, and grows with its human companion over the course<br />

of its life, a person who is fundamental to its own biological needs and to<br />

its identity. In short, in sharp contrast to anthropocentric thinking, from<br />

the process-relational perspective, neither the creative life-processes of<br />

human beings should be interpreted as standing condescendingly higher<br />

than Nature, 10 as in modernist humanism, nor should Nature be viewed<br />

as standing infinitely higher than human life, as in the biocentrism of<br />

radical anti-humanist ecologism.


40<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

In Part III of <strong>Process</strong> and Reality, entitled, “The Theory of Prehensions,”<br />

Whitehead seeks to provide both a cosmological and epistemological<br />

account of the creative processes of organisms by which they may determine<br />

their character, which also serves the aims of eco-psychology. This<br />

account stands in sharp contrast to ego-logical conceptions of the self with<br />

their basis in Cartesian substance-ontology, with its “assumption of bodies<br />

and minds as independent individual substances, each existing in its own<br />

right and apart from any necessary reference to each other” (SMW 194).<br />

To reiterate, Descartes had conceived of the self as a thinking substance<br />

(res cogitans) entirely separate from extended things (res extensa) and the<br />

natural world, which was defined as something dependent only upon<br />

itself in order to exist. Whitehead criticizes Descartes for mistaking the<br />

“privacy of mental life . . . for its substantial independence as an existent<br />

fact” (RM liii). In contrast, in Whiteheadian philosophy, the self cannot<br />

be described in terms of Descartes’ substances, defined as dependent on<br />

nothing for their existence, self-sustaining, entirely private, self-sufficient,<br />

and self-encapsulated (but also, it is not nothing). As he writes, “there<br />

is no entity, not even God ‘which requires nothing but itself in order to<br />

exist’” (RM 108), for example, God requiring His creatures in order to<br />

complete His own Creative or “superjective nature.” Furthermore, the<br />

process-relational standpoint is highly critical of determinations of “the<br />

value” of a thing or a “self” on the basis of how well it matches up with<br />

the concept of a substance as attributable to traditional notions of God. 11<br />

Undoubtedly, this view led to the individualism of modernity and the<br />

underlying drive to be God. Instead, for Whitehead, as Jones writes, the<br />

character “of any entity arises according to the relationships that entity<br />

sustains with all other entities” (RM xxi), every entity being “social,”<br />

namely, requiring the organic society of actual entities in its immediate<br />

environment in order to exist. In relation to the human organism, it is in<br />

this sense that Whitehead states that “man is a social animal” (PR 204).<br />

According to Whitehead, there are two interrelated “phases” which<br />

comprise the creative process of any organism, and by which it determines<br />

its character, one of appropriation and one of self-realization. Whereas<br />

appropriation involves the feeling, grasping, taking-account of, or seizing<br />

of elements of the natural world (as in the acquisition of food) for the<br />

sake of its existence so as to develop purposes, self-realization is the creative<br />

unfolding of an organism’s life-process or self-development through<br />

the actualization of such purposes. Self-realization always presupposes a


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

41<br />

previous activity of appropriation of elements from the world, whereas<br />

appropriation is informed by prior self-realizations and subjective aims.<br />

That is to say, Whitehead’s cosmology is constituted by a fundamental<br />

recognition that creative self-realization is only possible on the basis of<br />

appropriating the elements of the natural world, a notion that the modern<br />

worldview, in respect to the desire to be God, largely takes for granted.<br />

Whitehead’s epistemological stance is that of a “provisional realism,”<br />

which holds that concrete experience and grasping of “the natural” provides<br />

the starting point of the creative process. By way of the notion of a<br />

“prehension,” central in his epistemology, Whitehead means to describe<br />

an organism’s selective “appropriat[ion,] for the foundation of its own<br />

existence, the various elements of the universe out of which it arises” (PR<br />

219). 12 Whitehead’s notion of a “prehension” (Latin prehendere) has a dual<br />

meaning. It designates an organism’s feeling, or “uncognitive apprehension,”<br />

i.e. meaning “apprehension which may or may not be cognitive”<br />

(SMW 69). Simultaneously, it means an “appropriation” of the elements<br />

in its environment for the foundation of its own existence, namely, a<br />

“taking account of,” a grasping, a seizing, a “taking something in and<br />

making it part of the thing it has joined,” as in a “reception of expressions<br />

. . . (or of) the data for feeling diffused in the environment” (MT 23).<br />

A prehension might be said to be the unity of the causal impact of the<br />

data of our environment on the organism and the reception of that data.<br />

Prehensions also involve a process of selection of data, one based in the<br />

organism’s aims and interests. What Whitehead calls “positive prehensions”<br />

are feelings whereby data are positively included into the organism’s<br />

internal constitution, while negative prehensions are exclusions of data<br />

from entering into the organism’s internal constitution.<br />

In terms of human creativity and self-realization, the natural objects<br />

which are prehended provide the contents of mentality, including eternal<br />

objects, subjective aims, and purposes. This notion stands opposed to the<br />

idea of a substantial ego at the root of consciousness. For Whitehead, the<br />

“self” of a living human being is something which is in process and interrelated<br />

with the natural world. All of the contents of the self-realizational<br />

phases of the creative process are derived from an appropriation of the<br />

data issuing from the world. But, this observation neither “cheapens” the<br />

creative process or notions of “spirituality,” nor does it commit Whitehead<br />

to an atheistic position, as theologians and idealistic philosophers might<br />

claim. At the same time, Whitehead’s emphasis on creative process is


42<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

what distinguishes his standpoint from that of deconstructive postmodernism.<br />

In defending the notion that there are no subjective imaginings<br />

and purposes which contain contents that transcend the existents that we<br />

experience in the natural world, Whitehead’s notion of a prehension as a<br />

“process of appropriation” (PR 219) is of central importance. It implies<br />

that the self is largely the product of the prehensive process of feeling and<br />

appropriating the elements of the natural world. 13 Whitehead’s “provisionally<br />

realistic” stance, by which he maintains that the appropriations of past<br />

experience ground future self-realization, means that the self is not an ego,<br />

conceived as an independent substantial entity, transcendent of, and/or<br />

separated from the natural world. Since Whitehead’s cosmology alludes<br />

to the fact that in order to engage in the creative life-process, organisms<br />

must appropriate or prehend the elements of the natural world, both in<br />

terms of the physical resources that they need to live (e.g., food and water)<br />

as well as in terms of the mental resources via their past experience (with<br />

which they may develop and actualize fundamental purposes in the world),<br />

his epistemology and cosmology provide an implicit rationale for why<br />

human beings need to have reverence for the natural world. In this way,<br />

Whitehead’s theory of prehensions, as well as the interplay between the<br />

bodily and mental aspects (or “poles”) of organisms can be said to advance<br />

eco-psychology’s investigations and understanding of the relationship<br />

between the human self and the natural world. However, Whitehead’s<br />

“provisional realism” does not commit him to the point of view that<br />

human beings are Nature. They are not mere passive appropriators of “the<br />

natural” which thereby founds the totality of their Being. “The natural” as<br />

the content of Spirit is not simply read off via experience or through senseperception<br />

as it may be in Hume’s account. Not only are the conceptual<br />

operations of selection, re-enactment, valuation, and synthesis thoroughly<br />

involved in human creative processes, but “the natural,” as appropriated, is<br />

creatively transformed through such operations. While the contents of the<br />

human imagination and the human capacity for perception in the mode<br />

of symbolic reference are derived from past experience of the (natural)<br />

world, conceptual operations play a chief role in creativity.<br />

Admittedly, there are highly destructive or negative aspects at work<br />

in the particular creative processes attributable to human beings. In<br />

Whitehead’s theory of prehensions, negative prehensions are chiefly representative<br />

of the critical and destructive operations within the creative<br />

process. Negative prehensions are eliminations from feeling. In their


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

43<br />

fluctuating interplay with positive prehensions, negative prehensions<br />

are the ground of the operations of selective appropriation at the root of<br />

experience. In experience, while some data are felt to be relevant to human<br />

aims and positively prehended, other data are eliminated, negatively<br />

prehended, or dismissed from feeling. Human beings are perhaps the<br />

organisms who depend most highly upon an engagement with activities<br />

of negation and of negative prehension; negation, for Whitehead, being<br />

the peculiar, yet fundamental characteristic of consciousness. Negation<br />

is fundamental to human reasoning, yet, alluding to the deconstructive<br />

postmodernist stance, it is also its undoing. In this sense, for Whitehead,<br />

while every organism prehends both positively and negatively, an engagement<br />

in operations of negation and objectification factors highly into<br />

the particular character of “the human” in our contemporary epoch. In<br />

other words, of all organic species, human beings engage in operations<br />

of negation with the highest degree of intensity. This point may coincide<br />

with deconstructive postmodernist manners of thinking. At times,<br />

Derrida locates the context of deconstruction within creative play, but<br />

deconstruction also reveals an intent toward a totalizing destruction<br />

without further construction. Certainly, Sartre was fond of the term,<br />

“nihilation,” and as part of his phenomenological description of the initself-for-itself:<br />

“the only being that can be called free is the [one] that<br />

nihilates its being” (Existentialism 65). In other writings, I have pointed to<br />

the notion that Whitehead’s negative prehensions, in their contrast with<br />

positive prehensions, are the efficient cause of the creative process (Scarfe<br />

94). Whether an engagement with operations of negation belongs to the<br />

enduring character of humanity might be a topic for further discussion<br />

stemming from this paper. One might also inquire into the impact the<br />

human operations of negation, negative prehension, and selectivity (which<br />

enable the objectification and appropriation of “the natural”) have on<br />

the natural world as a whole. Nevertheless, from the process-relational<br />

standpoint, the distinction might be made that human beings are not<br />

merely libidinal animals, but also “appetitive” animals, pointing to their<br />

creative abilities.<br />

Against the imminent, deconstructionist counterclaim that Whitehead’s<br />

metaphysics of creativity is merely synonymous with Sartre’s notion<br />

of the pursuit of the in-itself-for-itself and the desire to be God, Whitehead’s<br />

emphasis on finitude and contingency of the creative processes of<br />

organisms points to the impossibility of the absolute correspondence of


44<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

the in-itself and the for-itself. Without the hope of self-realization, or<br />

a satisfaction implying the correspondence between potentiality/eternal<br />

objects and actuality/actual occasions, there would be no creative<br />

process. However, such a satisfaction is never constituted by a perfect,<br />

exact, complete, mirror-like, infinite one-to-one correspondence between<br />

them. But, even with its imperfections and “symbolic vaguenesses,” the<br />

correspondences that are achieved are still enough to satisfy the human<br />

organism’s quest for meaning. Whitehead admits that all organisms<br />

attempt to found their own Being as in the notion of causa-sui, “shar[ing]<br />

with God this characteristic of self-causation” (PR 222) and can be successful<br />

in defining and determining themselves qua “selves,” thereby<br />

satisfying Spinoza’s notion of a substance as being a causa sui. However,<br />

from the process-relational perspective, they never determine themselves<br />

in a way akin to being fully self-caused (causa sui), interpreted, in the<br />

purely substantialist sense, without recourse to their feelings of, appropriations<br />

of, and relations with other entities. Every organism requires its<br />

environment, which provides the data for the derivation of possibilities<br />

for its own self-creation. As such, the process of self-creation does not<br />

occur in a vacuum, as implied by substantialist philosophies. Rather, an<br />

entity is “the product of the efficient past.” (PR 150). Furthermore, as<br />

Whitehead writes, creative “adventure rarely reaches its predetermined<br />

end” (AI 379), imagination being unable to fully encapsulate actuality.<br />

Even if the satisfaction exhibits a high degree of correspondence between<br />

potentiality and actuality, all organic self-realization is subject to the ravages<br />

of perpetual perishing. At the same time, Whitehead goes to great<br />

lengths to show that the urge toward creative self-realization is not “mere<br />

wreckage,” (PR 346), since the organism, even through perishing, remains<br />

“everlasting” or “objectively immortal,” not to mention fueling further<br />

creative advance in the world.<br />

While human creativity can take on the form of “development,” it is<br />

definitely not reducible to it. One only need to point to the difference<br />

in terms of aesthetic value of a truck stop in contrast to Michelangelo’s<br />

painting of the Last Judgment above the altar of the Sistine Chapel in<br />

order to convey this distinction. Regardless, “sustainable development,”<br />

interpreted from the perspective of Whitehead’s critical non-anthropocentric<br />

organicism, is not to be defined in purely economic terms, as is<br />

common today, namely, as the ability to keep up a certain rate of economic<br />

growth. Rather, from a Whiteheadian stance, sustainability is to


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

45<br />

be construed in environmental terms. Sustainable development means<br />

striking a balance between the needs and wants of human populations<br />

and the natural ecology which sustains and supports life. It involves a<br />

serious effort to maintain a balance between the “ego-logical” and the<br />

“eco-logical,” between human self-realization and its appropriation of<br />

“the natural,” between human aims and the creative life-processes of other<br />

organisms, and beyond the “drives” corresponding with the desire to be<br />

God and the desire to be Nature, respectively.<br />

A stipulative definition of sustainable development from a processrelational<br />

perspective is two-fold. Sustainable development means, first,<br />

that because the Earth is a finite ecological system, the appropriation and<br />

extraction of resources, pollution emissions, habitat disruption, and the<br />

transformation of “the natural,” which are implied by the term “development,”<br />

should not exceed the regenerative capacity of the biosphere,<br />

as a whole, to absorb their effects. Second, it means that human beings<br />

should appropriate or consume resources at a rate which corresponds<br />

with the pace of their natural restoration or replenishment, as well as<br />

with cognizance of the needs of future generations. Sustainable development<br />

is about human beings using their reasoning capacities to restrain<br />

and to limit their appropriation and consumption of resources as well<br />

as the development and transformation of “the natural.” This stands in<br />

sharp contrast to blindly following the “human interest” in attempting<br />

to overcome Nature via technology, by both destroying it and ourselves<br />

in the process. Perhaps the most important factor in arriving at genuine<br />

sustainability is the limiting of human population growth, which reduces<br />

the net need for development and resource consumption, and, in turn,<br />

reduces the net impact on the natural environment.<br />

In relation to the issue of sustainability, Whitehead pointed out that<br />

“the function of reason is the direction of the attack on the environment”<br />

in order to secure the conditions for human survival and the perpetuation<br />

of human life, but further, “to live, to live well, to live better,” (FR 8). It<br />

must be noted here that Whitehead’s “is” here, descriptive of the current<br />

state of affairs at the time that he was writing this statement, is by no means<br />

a prescriptive “ought to be,” for according to constructive postmodernist<br />

philosophy, humanity’s over-exertion of its technical-rational faculties,<br />

characterized in terms of the desire to be God, has led to the over-development<br />

and the transformation of “the natural” beyond the bounds of<br />

planetary sustainability. In light of the ecological crisis, the aim to “live


46<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

better” must not be seen one-sidely to be synonymous with “attacking<br />

the environment” and pursuing development without novelty, but rather<br />

with adopting a way of life that takes the health of the biosphere into<br />

consideration; the health of the natural world being here associated with,<br />

but not reducible to, the well-being of human individuals. To illuminate<br />

this interrelationship, it stands to reason that if environmental conditions<br />

deteriorate, then human societies will become increasingly unable to<br />

guarantee the human rights and freedoms that we enjoy today. Hence, a<br />

defense of the environment is a long-term defense of human rights and<br />

the ability of human beings “to acquire an increase in [life] satisfaction”<br />

(FR 8). In applying Whitehead’s descriptions of the features of the creative<br />

process to the issue of sustainability, whereas the modern worldview aims<br />

to maximize human self-realization by way of maximizing the appropriation<br />

of “the natural” (largely taken for granted in the process), and<br />

whereas the extreme anti-humanism of radical ecologism aims to arrest<br />

both the appropriation of “the natural” as well as human self-realization,<br />

and, in turn, arresting human creativity in general, the process-relational<br />

environmental epistemology offers a sustainable “middle way” between the<br />

two. It points to the wisdom of tempering both contemporary society’s<br />

decadence, as well as each individual’s appropriation of “the natural” in<br />

terms of human self-actualization, while allowing for naturally sustainable<br />

levels of development, human creativity, life-satisfaction, and self-enjoyment.<br />

In Aristotelian language, Whitehead’s perspective is that of a return<br />

to the “golden mean” between extremes, for not only does immorality<br />

consist in a person’s thwarting of the ability, either in themselves or in<br />

another, to actualize their potential, as in the cases of alcoholism, anorexia,<br />

murder, theft, adultery, or withholding food or water from another, but<br />

conversely, it is also found in the vice of human self-maximization in<br />

relation to the actualization of one’s potentiality, beyond the bounds of<br />

planetary sustainability.<br />

Whitehead’s critical, non-anthropocentric organicism recognizes that<br />

it is in the highest interest of human beings to maintain the well-being<br />

of the natural world around them. “The natural,” for example, wild or<br />

undeveloped land not yet subordinate to human ends, ought not to be<br />

merely dismissed into irrelevance or negatively prehended in favor of<br />

development, for that which is wild or undeveloped is indeed relevant<br />

to human life. <strong>Process</strong>-relational philosophy holds that “the natural” has<br />

aesthetic value, which gives human beings pause to contemplate the deeper


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

47<br />

meaning of life. Whitehead stated that “our enjoyment of the values of<br />

human art, or of natural beauty, our horror at the obvious vulgarities and<br />

defacements which force themselves upon us [such as the destruction of<br />

“the natural”]—all these modes of experience . . . disclose the very meaning<br />

of things” (ESP 129, my addition). Whitehead’s epistemology depicts<br />

how feelings and emotions comprise the bedrock of experience and that<br />

our responses to objective states-of-affairs in the world, be they attracting<br />

or repulsing, are largely aesthetic valuations. Aesthetic judgments involve<br />

feelings of harmony or discordance, which arise from the causal efficacy<br />

of objects or events on us. As mentioned above, it is out of our experience<br />

of the natural world, namely, out of our feelings and our emotions,<br />

that we selectively develop subjective aims or fundamental purposes to<br />

be actualized in the world. Occasions which procure positive feelings are<br />

more apt to be selected than those which produce negative ones, in terms<br />

of how human beings develop such fundamental purposes.<br />

In Whitehead’s scheme, the aesthetic dimension of experience is the<br />

basis of consciousness, self-realization, as well as sound ethical intuitions.<br />

He goes to great lengths to discuss how aesthetic judgment involves the<br />

contrast of positive feelings (e.g., beauty, wonder, attraction, harmony,<br />

happiness) and negative feelings (e.g., repulsion, anxiety, horror, dislike,<br />

antagonism, suffering) in relation to the natural environment, thereby<br />

being cognizant of the fact that experiences of negative states-of-affairs<br />

have a fundamental role in giving meaning to human life. For instance,<br />

by experiencing environmental destruction first-hand, we become consciously<br />

aware that a correction of our behavior is necessary as part of<br />

our own self-development. But, Whitehead also holds that the domination<br />

of destructive discord, such as rampant destruction of the natural<br />

world, brings with it an “immediate feeling of evil, and the anticipation<br />

of destructive or weakened data for the future” (AI 263). Whitehead’s<br />

premise here is that since the aesthetic dimension of experience grounds<br />

our capacities for self-realization, the domination of aesthetic destruction<br />

(for example, in relation to huge tracts of rain-forest being clear-cut or<br />

burned down, or complete species being rendered extinct due to human<br />

negligence) also diminishes the human potentiality for self-realization, for<br />

richness of experience, and for novel modes of creativity, thus “robbing life<br />

of its zest for adventure” (AI 293). This diminishment can be conceived<br />

either in terms of the experience of present generations of human beings,<br />

or of future ones. For example, it is hard to imagine our children and


48<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

grandchildren living in a world where they will not be able to experience<br />

a polar bear, due to the species being rendered extinct. It should be obvious<br />

here that Whitehead’s discussion of aesthetic experience in relation<br />

to “the natural” provides insights which may augment eco-psychology’s<br />

investigation and treatment of the negative mental effects and traumas<br />

arising from the experience of environmental destruction.<br />

Whitehead’s cosmology also involves the ethical stance that the natural<br />

world has intrinsic value or value in-itself and that natural entities have<br />

value for the sake of themselves. This standpoint is not to be confused<br />

with the notion that an entity has its value in terms of how well it reflects<br />

the Cartesian notion of a substance. In Science and the Modern World,<br />

Whitehead contrasts his philosophy of organism with Descartes’ dualistic<br />

substance ontology and its effect on the human psyche, in relation<br />

to how it conceives of the natural world. Whitehead describes that with<br />

the intellectual rise of Cartesian substance ontology in early modernity,<br />

“the emergent individual value of each entity (was) transformed into the<br />

independent substantial existence of each entity . . . leading to an ascription<br />

of value to what is in itself valueless” (195). In short, according to<br />

Whitehead, Descartes’ materialistic perspective leads to a view of Nature<br />

as without intrinsic value. He charges that the notion of the “bare valuelessness<br />

of mere matter [leads] to a lack of reverence in the treatment<br />

of natural beauty,” in terms of aesthetic value, but it also furthered “the<br />

habit of ignoring the intrinsic worth of the environment” (196). Hence,<br />

for Whitehead, it is largely because of the dominance of the Cartesian<br />

worldview holding that the natural world is composed of barren material<br />

substances, purely mechanistic, devoid of life, and dependent only<br />

upon themselves in order to exist, that Nature was understood as devoid<br />

of inherent value. For if Nature is conceived of as a mere collection of<br />

bits of matter, hurrying purposelessly through empty space, then there<br />

is no reason to have respect for or to have appreciation for it as it is in<br />

itself. But, because of his claim that all existents, including inanimate<br />

objects (like rocks and dust) and organisms (like plants, plankton, and<br />

coral) are to be considered a part of the web of organic life, Whitehead’s<br />

cosmology provides a re-enchanted view of the natural world, namely, one<br />

teeming with life and re-invigorated with value, instead of being simply<br />

considered to be a lifeless material substance. While Whitehead’s notion<br />

of the mutual interdependence of actual entities or occasions does imply<br />

that every organism has instrumental value for all others, for him, each


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

49<br />

actual entity, taken independently, can also be said to have an individual<br />

life-history and an enduring self-identity which is part of the creative<br />

unfolding of the organic whole. That is to say, the intrinsic value of an<br />

actual entity is not to be defined merely in terms of how well it reflects<br />

the Cartesian conception of a substance, but rather in respect to the fact<br />

of its existence as part of the web of organic life.<br />

In outlining some of the main contours of the process-relational environmental<br />

ethic, in The Ethics of Creativity: Beauty, Morality, and Nature<br />

in a <strong>Process</strong>ive Cosmos, Brian Henning provides an analysis of Whitehead’s<br />

appeal to both the aesthetic and intrinsic value of “the natural,” although<br />

he emphasizes the former. Working on the premises that for Whitehead,<br />

“morality consists in the control of process, so as to maximize importance”<br />

(MT 13-14), and that “morality is always the aim at that union<br />

of harmony, intensity, and vividness which involves the perfection of<br />

importance for that occasion” (MT 13-14), Henning soundly argues<br />

toward a kalocentric ethic. A kalocentric ethic is one in which the most<br />

fundamental obligation human beings have is to act in such a way as to<br />

maximize beauty, value, and “greatness of experience” (MT 14) for the<br />

world as a whole, within the context of the specific situation and occasion.<br />

As Henning defines it, a kalocentric ethic is based in the notion that “an<br />

action is morally appropriate only if it would achieve the most beauty<br />

possible in the situation taken as a whole” (Ethics 192).<br />

This is not to suggest that the notions of “beauty” and “value” simply<br />

reside in mere subjective and anthropocentric judgments of taste, a<br />

perspective that comes as the result of not recognizing the holistic depth<br />

of Whitehead’s notion of “importance.” Henning is not here suggesting<br />

that the bulldozing of an ecologically vital swampland which appears<br />

to an individual as “an eyesore,” so as to build an aesthetically-pleasing<br />

cathedral, is justified. Rather, for Henning, value and importance here<br />

extend “not merely to the self but to others (the past actual occasions in<br />

an occasion’s actual world) and to the whole (the totality of achieved occasions)”<br />

(Ethics 133), although again, one cannot merely identify oneself<br />

as being that whole. Furthermore, while for Whitehead, “the generic aim<br />

of process is the attainment of importance” (MT 12, my emphasis), this<br />

is not to say that human creativity itself is implicitly “moral.” Rather, it is<br />

through realizing the aesthetic and the intrinsic value of “the natural,” and<br />

acting accordingly, namely, attaining a balance through controlling (e.g.,<br />

via reasoned direction, restraint, and self-limitation) the appropriations


50<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

and self-actualizations which constitute human creative processes, that<br />

the ethical path is to be found. In other words, since human creativity<br />

has been interpreted by many philosophers and theologians as a function<br />

of the desire to be God (e.g., living up to our human potential, having<br />

been made in “God’s image”) and/or the desire to be Nature, the ethical<br />

course of action is to avoid these extremes as well as the calamities that will<br />

befall us due to the vicious fluctuation between such extremes. Certainly,<br />

“sustainable development,” as has been re-defined above, is to be found in<br />

the control of the creative process (e.g., to limit the appropriation of “the<br />

natural”), and not simply in an appeal to the creative process itself. The<br />

point is that not all creativity is moral. Human creativity must be tempered<br />

by reasoned self-limitation, if it is to arrive at the requisite ecologically<br />

sustainable balance. To be sure, Henning notes, “the ‘maximization of<br />

importance’ aimed at in morality is made possible only by the ‘control<br />

of process’” (130). In any case, for our purposes here of setting out the<br />

contours of the process-relational environmental epistemology, I shall<br />

have to leave further considerations of a process-relational environmental<br />

ethic to a future work.<br />

From the “process-relational” environmental epistemology<br />

to the investigation of “constructive postmodern”<br />

environmental praxis<br />

The preceding analysis has elucidated some of the main contours of Whitehead’s<br />

process-relational environmental epistemology. In it, I have identified<br />

how it informs the various investigations of ecologically engaged psychology,<br />

such as those of eco-psychology, as well as offers novel proposals for environmentally<br />

ethical praxis. Specifically, with reference to characterizations of<br />

the modern and the deconstructive postmodern paradigms, as interpreted<br />

from the works of Sartre and Derrida, and involving the notions of “the<br />

desire to be God” and “the desire to be Nature,” respectively, this paper<br />

has demonstrated how Whitehead’s critical, non-anthropocentric organicism<br />

overcomes the vicious dichotomy between the ultimate aims of the<br />

anthropocentric humanism of modernity and the radical anti-humanism<br />

of deconstruction and radical ecologism. Parallel with the main problematic<br />

outlined by eco-psychology, the constructive postmodern paradigm is<br />

driven by an impetus to replace the dominant, ego-logical conceptions of<br />

the human self (for example, those advanced in mainstream psychology)<br />

which postulate it as a static ego, entirely separate from the natural world,


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

51<br />

devoid of process, and, in particular, as a Cartesian substance dependent<br />

only upon itself for its existence, with one conceived as thoroughly engaged<br />

in creative flux, organic, and thoroughly interconnected with the rest of the<br />

natural world, yet not simply definable by the latter. Environmentalist Bill<br />

McKibben’s statement in The End of Nature to the effect that the answer<br />

to the ecological crisis is not for humanity to simply disband our rational<br />

faculties, but to “exercise our reason to do what no other animal can do: we<br />

could limit ourselves voluntarily, choose to remain God’s creatures instead<br />

of making ourselves gods. . . . Such restraint . . . is the real challenge” (182-<br />

83) resonates, to a certain extent, with process-relational environmental<br />

epistemology. The “restraint” of which McKibben speaks may be achieved<br />

by recognizing human limitations as well as through “knowing ourselves,”<br />

namely, through a deeper understanding of the creative character of “the<br />

human” in this contemporary evolutionary epoch. Specifically, as has been<br />

alluded to in this paper, the process-relational environmental epistemology<br />

is largely constituted by the recognition of what the modern worldview takes<br />

for granted, namely, that “the natural” fuels all human creative processes,<br />

processes which constitute the self to begin with. In other words, it seeks<br />

to cultivate a heightened conscious awareness of the prehensive character<br />

of human life and experience in our culture, with a concern to limit the<br />

rate and extent of the appropriation, consumption, and destruction of “the<br />

natural” within human creative processes, thereby tempering the “attack<br />

on the environment” via reasoned self-limitation, while at the same time<br />

allowing for naturally sustainable levels of development, human creativity,<br />

life-satisfaction, and self-enjoyment. From the process-relational point of<br />

view, McKibben’s call for “restraint” will also entail an embracing of novel<br />

modes of human creativity which are not merely a function of instrumental<br />

reason, monetary gain, “development,” or “material appropriation,” but<br />

rather heighten the senses of both the aesthetic value and the intrinsic<br />

value of Nature.<br />

Notes<br />

1. In response to the possible charge that I am here committing Hume’s<br />

is/ought fallacy, one might hypothesize that if we confined our thought in<br />

the way that the unmitigated Hume would direct us, ethics would not even<br />

exist as a branch of philosophy. In matters pertaining to what human beings<br />

have control over, descriptions of what is can certainly lead to prescriptions<br />

for what should be, at the level of praxis.


52<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

2. See Chalquist, C. “Mind and Environment: A Psychological Survey of<br />

Perspectives Literal, Wide, and Deep.”Retrieved July 3, 2007.<br />

3. In Earth in the Balance, Al Gore makes constant reference to the assumed<br />

separation of “the human” and “the natural” as the major issue for environmentalism.<br />

For example, see pp. 218-19, 230-31, 237, 249-50, 257,<br />

262, 366.<br />

4. According to Sartre, the historical existence of a human being or of<br />

humanity precedes the definition of the essence of the self or of humanity.<br />

He states that atheistic existentialism holds to the position that “if God does<br />

not exist, there is at least one being in whom existence precedes essence,<br />

a being who exists before he can be defined by any concept, and that this<br />

being is man, or, as Heidegger says, human reality. What is meant here by<br />

saying that existence precedes existence? It means that, first of all, man exists,<br />

turns up, appears on the scene, and, only afterwards, defines himself. If man,<br />

as the existentialist conceives him, is indefinable, it is because at first he is<br />

nothing. Only afterward will he be something, and he himself will have<br />

made what he will be. Thus, there is no human nature, since there is no<br />

God to conceive it. Not only is man what he conceives himself to be, but<br />

he is also only what he wills himself to be after his thrust toward existence.<br />

Man is nothing else but what he makes of himself” (Existentialism 15).<br />

5. This is the case with German Idealism, especially, in Fichte’s die Tathandlung<br />

or Act of the “I’s” self-positing as absolute consciousness.<br />

6. It is to be mentioned here that Sartre’s phenomenological investigation<br />

of the meaning of desire as appropriation can be said to correspond closely<br />

with Heidegger’s notion of “the event of appropriation of Being” or “enowning”<br />

(Ereignis) as it relates to the essence of technology in Identity and<br />

Difference and The Onto-theological Constitution of Metaphysics. According<br />

to Heidegger, the essence of technology is made manifest by “enframing”<br />

(Ge-Stellen) which may be conceived of as an instrumental “prelude to . . .<br />

the event of appropriation [of Being]” (Identity 14), by which human beings<br />

treat Nature as a “standing-reserve,” setting it up in advance, in order to<br />

reveal its secrets and to extract its resources. Certainly, while Heidegger was<br />

not himself an environmental philosopher, many scholars have pointed out<br />

that the later Heidegger’s holistic philosophizing as well as his critique of<br />

technology in The Question Concerning Technology lend themselves well to<br />

environmentalist discourses. For example, as Devall and Sessions point out<br />

in Deep Ecology: Living as if Nature Mattered, Heidegger “concluded that<br />

[the] anthropocentric development [of Western philosophy since Plato]<br />

paved the way for the technocratic mentality which espouses domination<br />

over Nature” (98).


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

53<br />

7. For some deconstructionists, modernity has, for example, allowed for<br />

the patriarchal domination and oppression of non-European cultures by<br />

European cultures. In this respect, in rejecting the dominating meta-narratives<br />

of modernity, deconstruction can be said to lead to the liberation of<br />

peoples oppressed by modernity and to return to their own cultural identities<br />

and ways of life which are more harmonious with Nature. Especially,<br />

some strands of “Post-Colonial” theory ally themselves with deconstructive<br />

postmodernism and tend in this direction. As Clare Palmer describes it,<br />

“Post-Colonial” theory aims “to expose and to criticize the power-relations<br />

embedded in colonial regimes and in the relationships between societies<br />

that economically and politically dominate and societies and cultures that<br />

are dominated . . . usually on the basis that such power relations cause suffering<br />

and other kinds of harm (Response 51). It should be noted, however,<br />

that with respect to its alliance with the French deconstructionists, Post-<br />

Colonial theory has been criticized for itself being “strongly influenced by<br />

Continental European” philosophy (Keller 21) as well as accused of being<br />

the mere defense of cultural relativism.<br />

8. For example, see the article by W. S. Weed, “Can We Go To Mars<br />

Without Going Crazy?”<br />

9. Some scholars have sought to interpret Whitehead’s cosmology agnostically<br />

or even atheistically, namely, without reference to God, and others have done<br />

so in order to maintain the primacy of Darwinian evolution over intelligent<br />

design theories. Whitehead’s cosmological scheme can be said to be an attempt<br />

to synthesize these seemingly antagonistic perspectives. Whitehead’s cosmology<br />

was inspired by Darwin, but it also involves a claim that all organisms<br />

participate in creative processes which drive evolution. Whitehead’s notion<br />

of the creative process is not to be simply lumped in with Creationism. From<br />

a process-relational perspective, while contemporary science demonstrates<br />

that random mutations drive the evolutionary process and that there is no<br />

evidence of an intelligent designer or a direction toward an ultimate goal,<br />

scientists who reduce the evolution of species to genetics tend to omit the<br />

central fact that natural selection requires some reference to the life-process<br />

and the experience of organisms in determining whether such mutations are<br />

biologically successful. Similarly, without recourse to the creative processes<br />

of organisms, there is little room for an account for the intrinsic value of<br />

Nature; Nature, conceived as mere static bits of matter, being left “valueless”<br />

and “lifeless.” However, whether or not Whitehead can withstand the types<br />

of criticisms that were leveled against Bergson, especially in relation to the<br />

charge that his scheme is Lamarckian, is a subject matter for debate.<br />

10. This is not to say, for example, that following from this notion, a parent<br />

needs to allow a mosquito to suck the blood of its infant child (see


54<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

Henning 184). Rather, from the process-relational view, the parent ought<br />

to be selectively interested in the baby’s value as an intrinsically valuable<br />

organism, more so than a single mosquito, and therefore, she should protect<br />

it, for example, against the possibility of contracting the West Nile virus.<br />

However, at the same time, the parent does not need to carry out systematic<br />

acts of aggression against “the natural” as vengeance against the mosquito’s<br />

actions, fogging every corner of the planet in an attempt to destroy all<br />

mosquito species. Parents should understand that the mosquito’s selection<br />

of their particular baby as a food supply is a highly contingent event, that<br />

mosquitoes are an intrinsic part of the interconnected web of life, yet that<br />

there is, as part of human life, a need to deal with them (e.g., flick them<br />

off) when they are potentially in the process of causing harm to our loved<br />

ones. However, a reverential recognition of what Nature provides for us is<br />

important. At the very least, mosquitoes and their larvae provide food for<br />

fish that humans eat, and therefore parents ought to realize that reciprocal<br />

“trade-offs” between the aims of human beings and the maintenance of<br />

the wildness of the natural world are necessary in order to provide that<br />

balance necessary for a healthy planet as a whole. Especially important for<br />

parents, ethically speaking, should be a concern for the life-long health of<br />

their child, which will, in part, be a function of the maintenance of the<br />

health of the planet.<br />

11. In Religion in the Making, Whitehead quotes Descartes’ articulation<br />

in the Principles of Philosophy that “when we conceive of substance, we<br />

merely conceive an existent thing which requires nothing but itself in order<br />

to exist. To speak truth, nothing but God answers to this description as<br />

being that which is absolutely self-sustaining, for we perceive that there<br />

is no other created thing which can exist without being sustained by His<br />

power. . . . Created substances, however, whether corporeal or thinking,<br />

may be conceived under this common concept; for they are things which<br />

need only the concurrence of God in order to exist” (106). In the objections<br />

and replies to his Meditations, Descartes also states “the notion of a<br />

substance is just this—that it can exist by itself, that is without the aid of<br />

any other substance. And there is no one has ever perceived two substances<br />

by means of two different concepts without judging that they really are<br />

distinct” (Selected 146).<br />

12. A strong parallel can be drawn here between Sartre’s phenomenological<br />

investigation of the desire to be as an activity of appropriation and<br />

Whitehead’s notion of a prehension. However, the distinction to be made<br />

here is that it is apparent that Whitehead is using the word “foundation,”<br />

not in the sense of becoming self-caused, in the purely substantialist sense,<br />

but in the sense of any organism’s, human or nonhuman, maintenance of<br />

its own existence through a selective appropriation, in the organic sense.


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

55<br />

For Whitehead, the reality is that in the natural world, “life is robbery”<br />

(PR 105).<br />

13. Whitehead would here seem to agree with Heidegger in relation to the<br />

question of metaphysics that “Being grounds beings, and beings, as what<br />

is most of all, account for Being” (Identity 69).<br />

Works cited<br />

Ausubel, K. “Interview.” The Eleventh Hour. Warner Bros. Documentary,<br />

2007.<br />

Beauvoir, S. de, Adieux: A Farewell to Sartre. Trans. P. O’Brian. London:<br />

Penguin, 1984.<br />

Chalquist, C. “Mind and Environment: A Psychological Survey of Perspectives<br />

Literal, Wide, and Deep.” 2006: 1-26. .<br />

Derrida, J. The Ear of the Other. New York: Schocken, 1985.<br />

___. “The Ends of Man.” After Philosophy: End or Transformation? Ed. K.<br />

Baynes, et al. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987. 125-58.<br />

___. Of Grammatology. Trans. C. Spivak. Baltimore: John Hopkins UP,<br />

1997.<br />

___. “The Animal That Therefore I am.” Critical Inquiry 28 (2002): 369-418.<br />

.<br />

Descartes, R. Selected Philosophical Writings. Trans.J. Cottingham, et al. New<br />

York: Cambridge UP, 1988.<br />

Devall, B. and G. Sessions, et al. Deep Ecology: Living as if Nature Mattered.<br />

Layton, Utah: Gibbs Smith, 1985.<br />

Felt, J.W. “Whitehead’s Misconception of ‘Substance’ in Aristotle.” <strong>Process</strong><br />

<strong>Studies</strong> 14 (1985): 224-36.<br />

Fisher, A. “Toward a More Radical Ecopsychology: Therapy for a Dysfunctional<br />

Society.” Alternatives 22 (1996): 20-26.<br />

___. Radical Ecopsychology: Psychology in the Service of Life. Albany: State U<br />

of New York P, 2002.<br />

Freadman, R. et al. Re-thinking Theory: A Critique of Contemporary Literary<br />

Theory and an Alternative Account. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1994.<br />

Glendinning, C. “Technology, Trauma, and the Wild.” Ecopsychology: Restoring<br />

the Earth, Healing the Mind. Ed. T. Roszak, et al. San Francisco:<br />

Sierra Club, 1995. 41-54.<br />

Gore, A. Earth in the Balance: Ecology and the Human Spirit. New York:<br />

Rodale, 1992.<br />

Griffin, D.R., et al. Spirituality and Society: Postmodern Visions. Albany: State<br />

U of New York P, 1988.


56<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

___. “Introduction to the SUNY Series in Constructive Postmodern<br />

Thought.” Higher Education in the Making. Ed. G. Allan. Albany: State<br />

U of New York P, 2004. xi-xv.<br />

Habermas, J. Knowledge and Human Interests. Trans. J. Shapiro. Boston:<br />

Beacon Press, 1971.<br />

Heidegger, M. Being and Time. Trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. New<br />

York: Harper San Francisco, 1962.<br />

___. Identity and Difference. Trans. and intro. J. Stambaugh. Chicago: U<br />

of Chicago P, 1969.<br />

Henning, B.G. The Ethics of Creativity: Beauty, Morality, and Nature in a<br />

<strong>Process</strong>ive Cosmos. Pittsburgh: U of Pittsburgh P, 2005.<br />

Husserl, E. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology.<br />

Trans. D. Carr. Evanston: Northwestern UP, 1970.<br />

___. Cartesian Meditations. Trans. D. Cairns. Boston: Kluwer, 1991.<br />

Keller, C. “Connections of Difference: Sexes and Ecologies,” <strong>Process</strong> Thought<br />

and East Asian Culture Conference Proceedings: Keynote Lectures, Seoul,<br />

Korea, 2004: Whitehead Society of Korea and the International <strong>Process</strong><br />

Network, 21-27.<br />

Kidner, D.W. “Why Psychology is Mute About the Environmental Crisis.”<br />

Environmental Ethics 16 (1994): 359-75.<br />

___. Nature and Psyche: Radical Environmentalism and the Politics of Subjectivity.<br />

Albany: State U of New York P, 2002.<br />

Lewandowski, J.D. “Modernity and Its Vicissitudes.” Cultural Critique 29<br />

(1994-95): 139-62.<br />

Lyotard, J-F. “The Postmodern Condition.” After Philosophy: End or Transformation?<br />

Ed. K Baynes, et al. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987.<br />

73-94.<br />

McKibben, B. The End of Nature. New York: Random House, 1989.<br />

Metzner, R. “The Psychopathology of the Human-Nature Relationship.”<br />

Ecopsychology: Restoring the Earth, Healing the Mind. Ed. T. Roszak, et<br />

al. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1995. 55-67.<br />

Naess, A. “Heidegger, Postmodern Theory and Deep Ecology.” Trumpeter<br />

14 (1997): 1-7. .<br />

Nietzsche, F. The Portable Nietzsche. Trans. W. Kaufmann. New York: Viking<br />

Penguin, 1968.<br />

Norris, C. Deconstruction: Theory and Practice. New York: Routledge,<br />

1991.<br />

Palmer, C. “Response to Cobb and Menta.” <strong>Process</strong> <strong>Studies</strong> 33 (2004):<br />

46-70.


Scarfe/<strong>Overcoming</strong> <strong>Anthropocentric</strong> Humanism<br />

57<br />

Peters, M.A. “Derrida, Pedagogy and the Calculation of the Subject.” Educational<br />

Philosophy and Theory 35 (2003).<br />

Pierce, J. Morality Play: Case <strong>Studies</strong> in Ethics. Toronto: McGraw-Hill,<br />

2005.<br />

Roszak, T. The Voice of the Earth: An Exploration of Ecopsychology. Toronto:<br />

Simon and Schuster, 1992.<br />

___. “The Nature of Sanity.” Psychology Today, January-February 1996, 1-<br />

3, .<br />

Sartre, J.-P. Being and Nothingness. Trans. H. Barnes. New York: Washington<br />

Square Press, 1956.<br />

___. “Existentialism is a Humanism.” Existentialism From Dostoevsky to Sartre.<br />

Ed. and trans. W. Kaufman. New York: Penguin, 1975, 345-69.<br />

___. Existentialism and Human Emotions. Trans. B. Frechtman and H.E.<br />

Barnes. New York: Carol Publishing, 1985.<br />

___. Nausea. Trans. L. Alexander. New York: New Directions, 1964.<br />

___. The Transcendence of the Ego. Trans. F. Williams and R. Kirkpatrick.<br />

New York: Hill and Wang, 1960.<br />

Scarfe, A. “Negative Prehensions and the Creative <strong>Process</strong>,” <strong>Process</strong> <strong>Studies</strong><br />

32 (2003): 94-105.<br />

Stack, G. Nietzsche: Man, Knowledge, and Will to Power. New York: Aperture,<br />

1994.<br />

Weed, W.S. “Can We Go To Mars Without Going Crazy?” Discover Magazine,<br />

May 1, 2001.< http://discovermagazine.com/2001/may/cover>.<br />

Whitehead, A.N. Adventures of Ideas (AI). 1933. New York: Free Press,<br />

1967.<br />

___. The Concept of Nature (CN). 1920. New York: Cambridge UP, 1995.<br />

___. Dialogues of Alfred North Whitehead (as recorded by Vincent Price).<br />

Boston: Little, Brown, 1954.<br />

___. Essays in Science and Philosophy (ESP). New York: Philosophical Library,<br />

1948.<br />

___. The Function of Reason (FR). 1929. Boston: Beacon, 1969.<br />

___. “Mathematics and the Good (MG).” The Library of Living Philosophers,<br />

Vol. 3: The Philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead. Ed. P.A. Schilpp. New<br />

York: Tudor, 1951. 666-81.<br />

___. Modes of Thought (MT). 1938. New York: Free Press, 1968.<br />

___. <strong>Process</strong> and Reality (PR). 1929. Corrected Edition. Ed. D.R. Griffin<br />

and D.W. Sherburne. New York: Free Press, 1978.<br />

___. Religion in the Making (RM). 1926. Intro. J.A. Jones. New York:<br />

Fordham UP, 1996.


58<br />

PROCESS STUDIES SUPPLEMENTS 12 (2008)<br />

___. Science and the Modern World (SMW). 1925. New York: Free Press,<br />

1967.<br />

Wood, D. The Deconstruction of Time. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities<br />

Press International, 1989.<br />

Zaner, R.M. “Discussion of Jacques Derrida, ‘The Ends of Man.’” Philosophy<br />

and Phenomenological Research 32 (1972): 384-89.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!